Aristotle: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Gareth Leng
mNo edit summary
 
(96 intermediate revisions by 27 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Aristotle''' ([[Greek language|Greek]]: {{polytonic|Ἀριστοτέλης}}, ''Aristotélēs'') (384–[[March 7]] [[322]] [[Common Era|BCE]]) was an [[Ancient Greece|ancient Greek]] [[greek philosophy|philosopher]], a student of [[Plato]] and teacher of [[Alexander the Great]]. Books on diverse subjects are attributed to him, about [[metaphysics]], [[physics]], [[zoology]], [[botany]], [[logic]], [[rhetoric]], [[poetry]], [[politics]], and [[government]]. Aristotle, with Plato and [[Socrates]], was among the most influential of the [[Greek philosophy|ancient Greek philosophers]]. They took [[Presocratic philosophy]], which was enigmatic and vague, and created the first very large, detailed, systematic, and rationally-defended systems of thought.  Aristotle's system of thought, in particular, is surely one of the widest-ranging in history.  In addition, Plato and Aristotle founded two of the most important schools of ancient philosophy.
{{subpages}}
{{TOC|right}}
{{Image|Bust of Aristotle.jpg|left|350px|A marble bust of Aristotle.}}
'''Aristotle''' (Ancient [[Greek]]: ''Ἀριστοτέλης, Aristotélēs''), a Greek [[Philosopher|philosopher]] of the fourth century BCE, was born just in time to know [[Plato]], another influential philosopher, and worked on many diverse subjects with unusual taxonomical zeal.  


Although Aristotle wrote dialogues early in his career, only fragments of these have survived. The works of Aristotle that exist today are in [[treatise]] form and were mostly unpublished texts, generally thought to be lecture notes or texts used by his students. Among the most important are ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'', ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]] (or [[Ontology]])'', ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'', ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'', ''[[De Anima]] (On the Soul)'' and ''[[Poetics]]''. These works, although connected in many fundamental ways, differ significantly in both style and substance.  
Aristotle was particularly interested in observing nature and his writings on biology were much admired by [[Charles Darwin]] amongst others. Throughout the Middle Ages, no other thinker had as great an influence as Aristotle, and he merited in the thirteenth century alone some five separate Papal bans. Today, Aristotle's legacy remains in many fields of endeavour and he is usually considered one of the great foundational figures of both philosophy and natural science.


Aristotle studied almost every subject possible at the time, probably being one of the first [[polymath]]s. In science, Aristotle studied [[anatomy]], [[astronomy]], [[economics]], [[embryology]], [[geography]], [[geology]], [[meteorology]], [[physics]], and [[zoology]]. In philosophy, Aristotle wrote on [[aesthetics]], [[ethics]], [[government]], [[metaphysics]], [[politics]], [[psychology]], [[rhetoric]] and [[theology]]. He also dealt with [[education]], foreign customs, [[literature]] and [[poetry]]. His combined works practically constitute an [[encyclopedia]] of Greek knowledge.
==Early years==
{{Image|ClassicalGreece.gif|left|350px|Greece at the time of Aristotle (Chalcidic Peninsula lays between Thrace and Macedonia at the north-west edge of the Aegean Sea.) Source: U.S.M.A.}}


== Biography ==
Born in 384 BCE in Stagirus (alternately Stagira or Stageirus), a small town in northern Greece on the Chalcidic Peninsula, to Nicomachus, a medical doctor, and Phaestis, his mother, Aristotle’s family was probably native to that area.  
===Early life and studies at the Academy===
Aristotle was born in a [[apoikia|colony]] of [[Andros]] on the [[Macedon]]ian peninsula of [[Chalcidice]] in 384 BCE. His father, Nicomachus, was court physician to King [[Amyntas III of Macedon]]; it is believed that Aristotle's ancestors held this position under various kings of the Macedons. Little is known of his mother, Phaestis; she died while Aristotle was very young. When Nicomachus also died, in Aristotle's tenth year, he was placed under the guardianship of his uncle, [[Proxenus of Atarneus]], who taught Aristotle [[Greek language|Greek]], [[rhetoric]], and [[poetry]] (O'Connor ''et al.'', 2004). Aristotle also attended Plato's school for young Greek aristocracy, and became Plato's favourite student. Aristotle was also influenced by his father's medical knowledge; when he went to [[Athens]] at the age of eighteen, he was probably already trained in the investigation of natural phenomena.


From the age of eighteen to thirty-seven, Aristotle remained in Athens as a pupil of Plato. The relations between Plato and Aristotle have been the subject of various legends, many of which depict Aristotle unfavourably. No doubt there were divergences of opinion between Plato, who took his stand on sublime, idealistic principles, and Aristotle, who even then preferred investigating the facts and laws of the physical world. It is also probable that Plato suggested that Aristotle needed restraining rather than encouragement, but Aristotle's conduct after the death of Plato, his continued association with [[Xenocrates]] and other [[Platonism|Platonists]], and his allusions in his writings to Plato's doctrines indicate that while there were differences of opinion between Plato and Aristotle, there was cordial appreciation and mutual forbearance.
Traditionally a son followed his father’s profession or trade. However, Nicomachus died when Aristotle was a boy. Prior to that death, there is reason to believe that his father’s influence was significant. At the time, patients did not got to doctors, doctors went their patients. It is not unreasonable to think Aristotle accompanied his father on his travels.


===Aristotle as philosopher and tutor===
Nicomachus found work more to his preferences in the neighboring state of Macedonia and he was eventually appointed personal physician to Amyntas III, the king of Macedonia, in the capitol, Pella. This was the King Amyntas whose son Philip successfully united a number of the Greek city states after defending Macedonia, and he in turn was the father of Alexander, The Great. Aristotle was almost the exact age as Philip and it is likely that they were acquainted if not actually friends. Later in life Philip was to support some of Aristotle’s ambitions, if only for a time, indicating that they agreed on some things and enjoyed some measure of trust.
After Plato's death in 347 BCE, Aristotle was considered as the next head of the Academy, a position eventually awarded to Plato's nephew. Aristotle then went with Xenocrates to the court of [[Hermias]], ruler of [[Atarneus]] in [[Asia Minor]], married his niece, Pythias, and with her had a daughter named Pythias after her mother. In 344 BCE, Hermias was murdered in a rebellion, <!--''(or a Persian attack?)''--> and Aristotle went with his family to [[Mytilene]]. It is reported that he stopped on [[Lesbos Island|Lesbos]] and briefly conducted biological research. Then, one or two years later, he was summoned to Pella, the Macedonian capital, by King [[Philip II of Macedon]] to become the tutor of Alexander the Great, who was then thirteen.


[[Plutarch]] wrote that Aristotle imparted to Alexander a knowledge of ethics and politics, and the 'most profound secrets' of philosophy. Alexander profited by contact with the philosopher, and Aristotle made prudent and beneficial use of his influence over the young prince (although [[Bertrand Russell]] disputes this). Alexander provided Aristotle with ample means for the acquisition of books and the pursuit of his scientific investigation. It is possible that Aristotle also participated in the education of Alexander's boyhood friends, which may have included [[Hephaestion]] and [[Harpalus]]. Aristotle maintained a long correspondence with Hephaestion, eventually collected into a book, unfortunately now lost.
Nicomachus died about the time Aristotle was 10 years old. As a consequence he did not become a physician. Although it is not absolutely clear from the evidence we have, it would also seem that his mother Phaestis, died while Aristotle was young


According to Plutarch and [[Diogenes]], Philip had Aristotle's hometown of Stageira burned during the 340s BCE, and Aristotle successfully requested that Alexander rebuild it. During his tutorship of Alexander, Aristotle was reportedly considered a second time for leadership of the Academy; his companion Xenocrates was selected instead.
Aristotle’s future was then in the hands of a guardian, Proxenus of Atarneus, who might have been an uncle or a family friend. Proxenus was a teacher of Greek, rhetoric, and poetry, which presumably would have rounded out the teaching in biological topics Aristotle had received from his father. Aristotle’s prose written later in life was of such quality that it seems reasonable to think he was also taught this subject when he was young.<ref name=KingPembrokeLife>[http://users.ox.ac.uk/~worc0337/authors/aristotle.html Aristotle Life and Work] King, Peter J.,  Pembroke College, Oxford University</ref><ref name=MacTutorAristotle>[http://www-gap.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Biographies/Aristotle.html Aristotle Biography] O'Connor, John J.  and Robertson, Edmund F. (1999). ''MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive'', School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland</ref>


===Founder and master of the Lyceum===
===Plato's Academy===
In about 335 BCE, Alexander departed for his Asiatic campaign, and Aristotle, who had been his informal adviser since Alexander ascended the Macedonian throne, returned to Athens and opened his own school of philosophy. He may, as [[Aulus Gellius]] says, have conducted a school of rhetoric during his former residence in Athens; but now, following Plato's example, he gave regular instruction in philosophy in a [[gymnasium (ancient Greece)|gymnasium]] dedicated to [[Apollo Lyceios]], from which his school came to be known as the [[Lyceum]]. (It was also called the [[Peripatetic]] School because Aristotle preferred to discuss problems of philosophy with his pupils while walking around (''peripateo'') the shaded walks (''peripatoi'') around the gymnasium.)
In 367, at the age of 17, he was sent to [[Athens]] where he entered Plato’s Academy and remained there for twenty years.  It is not clear why Aristotle went to Athens; perhaps he had read Plato’s dialogues while in Stagira and wanted to study with him in particular or maybe Athens was simply the place to study at the time.  During those twenty years, Aristotle was not simply a pupil; he carried out independent studies in natural science, and led lectures especially on the subject of rhetoric. [[Plato]] died in 347 and leadership of the Academy was passed on to his nephew Speusippus, who best represented the teachings of Plato.  While Plato lived, Aristotle was a loyal member of the Academy; however even then, Aristotle’s thoughts on important points began to diverge from Platonism.  Perhaps due to his growing dissatisfaction with the curriculum of the Academy or to anti-Macedonian feeling at Athens due to political unrest, Aristotle accepted an invitation from Hermeias, a former fellow-student in the Academy turned ruler of Atarneus and Assos, on the coast of Asia minor.


Aristotle composed most of his writings in the thirteen years (335&ndash;322 BCE) that he spent as teacher of the Lyceum. Imitating Plato, he wrote ''[[Dialogue]]s'' in which his doctrines were expounded in somewhat popular language. He also composed treatises on physics, metaphysics in which the exposition is more [[didactic]] and the language more technical than in the ''Dialogues''. These writings brought together the works of his predecessors in Greek philosophy, and how he pursued his investigations of natural phenomena. [[Pliny the Elder]] claimed that Alexander placed under Aristotle's orders all the hunters, fishermen, and fowlers of the royal kingdom and all the overseers of the royal forests, lakes, ponds and cattle-ranges. Aristotle was fully informed about the doctrines of his predecessors, and [[Strabo]] asserted that he was the first to accumulate a great library.
===Years at Atarneus===
He remained in Atarneus for three years and married Pythias, niece of Hermeias, who bore him a daughter of the same name. After the death of his first wife, his second wife Herpyllis, a native to Stagira, bore him a son, Nicomachus, after whom the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' were named. At the end of three years, Aristotle moved to Mitylene, a neighboring island of Lesbos. Aristotle’s works suggest that he devoted part of his time in the Aegean to the study of marine biology.


In the last years of his life, relations between Aristotle and Alexander were strained, owing to the disgrace and punishment of [[Callisthenes]], whom Aristotle had recommended to Alexander. Nevertheless, Aristotle continued to be regarded as a friend of Alexander and a representative of Macedonia. Consequently, when Alexander's death became known in Athens, and the outbreak occurred which led to the [[Lamian war]], Aristotle shared in the general unpopularity of the Macedonians. The charge of [[impiety]], which had been brought against [[Anaxagoras]] and [[Socrates]], was now brought against Aristotle. He left the city, saying, "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy" (''Vita Marciana'' 41). He took up residence at his country house at [[Chalcis]], in [[Euboea]], and died there the following year, 322 BCE. His death was due to a disease, reportedly 'of the stomach', from which he had long suffered; the story that his death was due to [[Conium|hemlock]] poisoning, as well as the legend that he threw himself into the sea "because he could not explain the [[tide]]s," are without historical foundation.
===Relocating to Pella===
In 343, Philip of Macedon, in succession to his father Amyntas, invited Aristotle to undertake the education of his thirteen year old son, Alexander, who later would become [[Alexander the Great]]. Little to nothing is known about the education of Alexander but it is probably during this time that Aristotle turned his attention to political subjects. In 340, Alexander was appointed regent for his father and his pupillage ended.  Subsequently, Aristotle may have settled in Stagira.


Aristotle's legacy had a profound influence on Islamic thought and philosophy during the [[Middle Ages]]. Muslim thinkers such as [[Avicenna]], [[Al-Farabi]], and Yaqub ibn Ishaq al-Kindi<ref name="kindi">http://www.ummah.net/history/scholars/KINDI.html</ref> were some of the major proponents of the Aristotelian school of thought during the ''[[Golden Age of Islam]]''.
===Death of Philip and Establishing the Lyceum===
In 335, soon after Philip’s assassination, Aristotle returned to Athens and though the Academy flourished under new leadership, he preferred to set up his own school called the [[Lyceum (Aristotle)|Lyceum]]. Every morning at the Lyceum, Aristotle and his students discussed the more abstruse philosophical matters such as logic, physics and metaphysics and in the afternoon and evenings held lectures/discussions in more popular matters such as rhetoric and politics.  Shortly after the death of Alexander the Great in 323, anti-Macedonian feelings swept over Athens and Aristotle, once again, left Athens and retired to Chalcis, where his mother’s family had estates.  Soon after, in 322, he died.<ref>Ross, D. ''Aristotle''. Routledge Press, 2004. 336 pp.</ref><ref>Barnes, J. ''The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle''. Cambridge University Press, 1995. 404 pp.</ref>


== Methodology ==
==The works of Aristotle==
''Please refer to this page’s catalog for a complete list of Aristotle’s works, and to the subpage on the [[spurious works of Aristotle]].''


Aristotle defined his philosophy as "the science of the universal [[essence]] of that which is [[actual]]", in contrast to Plato's definition of it as the 'science of the [[idea]]', the unconditional basis of [[phenomena]]. Both regarded philosophy as concerned with the [[Universality (philosophy)|universal]], but Aristotle found the universal in [[particular]] things, and called it the essence of things, while Plato held that the universal exists apart from particular things, and is related to them as their [[prototype]] or [[exemplar]]. For Aristotle, philosophical method implies the ascent from the study of particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences, while for Plato it means the descent from a knowledge of universal ideas to a contemplation of particular imitations of those ideas. In a sense, Aristotle's method is both [[Inductive reasoning|inductive]] and [[Deductive reasoning|deductive]], while Plato's is deductive from ''[[a priori]]'' principles.
Though much of Aristotle’s thought is historically interesting, it is also fascinating because it is a comprehensive picture of the world that differs, in some ways dramatically, from that of modern people. The works of Aristotle, however, can be daunting to the uninitiated.  


For Aristotle, "natural philosophy" corresponded to the phenomena of the natural world, including [[Motion (physics)|motion]], [[light]], and the [[laws of physics]]. Many centuries later, these subjects would become the basis of modern science, and the term "philosophy" has come to be narrowly understood as metaphysics, distinct from empirical study of the natural world. However, for Aristotle, philosophy encompassed all facets of intellectual inquiry, and he made philosophy coextensive with [[reasoning]], which he also called 'science'. His use of the term "science" has a different meaning to that which is covered by the scientific method: "All science (''dianoia'') is either practical, poetical or theoretical". By "practical" science, he meant ethics and politics; by "poetical", he means the study of poetry and the other fine arts; while by 'theoretical philosophy' he meant physics, [[mathematics]], and metaphysics, defined as "the knowledge of [[immaterial]] being", the "theological science", or of "being in the highest degree of abstraction". If logic, or, as Aristotle calls it, [[analytic]], is regarded as a study preliminary to philosophy, we have as divisions of Aristotelian philosophy:
Unlike the carefully presented and highly literary works of Plato, the works of Aristotle tend to be terse and pithy, and to an extreme extent. In fact, the works of Aristotle which survive to the present day seem to be something like lecture notes.<ref>p. 3, Barnes
# [[Logic]]
</ref>
# Theoretical philosophy, including [[metaphysics]], [[physics]], [[mathematics]]
In addition to the prose style of Aristotle’s extant works, his texts are also made difficult by their frequently piecemeal nature. A comparison with Plato is again useful. Plato’s works are made to be read by an individual reader, and are generally self-contained. Aristotle’s works, as lecture notes, refer only briefly to important concepts that are not strictly relevant to the subject at hand. For example, much of his work is underlain by his conviction that particulars are [[ontology|ontologically]] prior to [[universals]], but this idea is only explained at length in a couple of places. It’s worth observing that Aristotle, as a lecturer, would have been able to leave the topic at hand and explain any important ideas his listeners were unfamiliar with.
# Practical philosophy
# Poetical philosophy


==Aristotle's epistemology==
It is also important not to underestimate the difficulties that Aristotle’s language creates. Aristotle wrote in Ancient Greek, but it is not a Greek which translates easily to normal-sounding English. Aristotle makes liberal use of technical terms. For example, ‘form’ and ‘knowledge’ in English are each the best translation for three separate Greek words which Aristotle uses with different shades of meaning. He does not, however, use these terms consistently.
===Logic===


Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic until the advances in [[mathematical logic]] in the 19th century. [[Kant]] himself thought that Aristotle had done everything possible in terms of logic.
The style and organization of his works are not always negatives. Aristotle is made easier reading by the fact that his works frequently follow a predictable form. He often begins one of his investigations by stating the conclusions of earlier thinkers: frequently Plato, but other thinkers as well. <ref>This is connected with his valuation of ‘reasonable opinions.’ Cf. the discussion at Barnes, 15ff.</ref> Then, he moves to a consideration of the problems, or aporiai, with a given idea, and he finally states his opinion-- before moving to a discussion of the problems with his opinion! (It can be helpful for the reader to highlight, underline, or otherwise mark the proposition Aristotle is espousing.)


==Ideas, method and achievements <ref>'A large part of an early version of this section was taken from the entry on Aristotle in 'Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics', edited by Martin Cohen, (Hodder Arnold 2006) and donated to the Citizendium by the author.'' </ref>==


Neither Aristotle nor the other Greek philosophers made any distinction between scientific and philosophical investigations. Aristotle was particularly interested in observing nature and his biology was much admired by [[Darwin]] amongst others. Aristotle influenced subsequent studies by his view that organisms had a function, were striving towards some purposeful end, and that nature is not haphazard. If plant shoots are observed to bend towards the light they are ‘seeking the light’. The function of mankind is, he suggests, to reason, as this is what people are better at than any other member of the animal kingdom - ‘Man is a rational animal’. This approach is in contrast to that of today's biologist or scientist who try to explain things by reference to ‘mechanisms’.


====Analytics and the ''Organon''====
===Political ideas===
What we today call "Aristotelian logic", Aristotle himself would have called "analytics"; he reserved the term "logic" to mean "dialectics"His logical works were compiled into six books in about the early 1st century CE:
Aristotle marks the watershed in Greek philosophy, born fifteen years after the execution of [[Socrates]] in 399 B.C.E, studying at the Academy in Athens under [[Plato]] until B.C.E 347. Although he had hoped to become Plato's successor, in fact Aristotle's approach was was out of favour with the mathematicians of the time, and Plato's nephew, Speussippus took over instead. After this Aristotle left  Greece for Asia Minor where  for the next five years he concentrated on developing his philosophy and biology. He then returned to Macedonia to be tutor to the future Alexander the Great, but there is little evidence of him influencing his pupil and indeed Aristotle seems to have been largely oblivious to the social and geo-political changes that were already making his approach to politics largely irrelevant.
#''Categories''
#''On Interpretation''
Indeed, even whilst Aristotle was teaching about the ''polis'' in the Lyceum, Alexander was already planning an empire in which he would rule the whole of Greece and Persia, in the process producing a new society in which both Greeks and barbarians would become, as [[Plutarch]] later put it, ‘one flock on a common pasture’ feeding under one law. In fact, whilst Aristotle wrote on the case of the 'polis', for almost two millennia the area was to see no city states, but instead a succession of empires. The rule of Macedonia, of Rome, and of Charlemagne came and went, with Aristotle not even so much as a footnote. Yet for much of this time, Aristotle was widely studied in the Islamic world, where he was hailed as 'the wise man' and his texts were carefully preserved. In  the Middle Ages his ideas were 'rediscovered' by  St Thomas Aquinas and, especially given the effective marriage of the Catholic Church with the state, became highly influential.
#''Prior Analytics''
#''Posterior Analytics''
#''Topics''
#''On Sophistical Refutations''


The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialetics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). There is one volume of Aristotle's concerning logic not found in the ''Organon'', namely the fourth book of ''Metaphysics''. (Bocheński, 1951).
Aristotle was similarly concerned at the fractious nature of the Greek city states in his time, the fourth century B.C.E. The states were small, but that did not stop them continually splitting into factions that fought amongst themselves. A whole book of Aristotle’s political theory is devoted to this problem. And Aristotle shared Plato's aversion to tyranny, warning that under such government, all citizens would be constantly on view, and a secret police ‘like the female spies employed at Syracuse, or the eavesdroppers sent by the tyrant Hiero to all social gatherings’ would be employed to sow fear and distrust. For these are the essential and characteristic hallmarks of tyrants.
Aristotle sees the origin of the state differently from Plato, stating explicitly that ‘a State is not a sharing of a locality for the purpose of preventing mutual harm and promoting trade.’ True to his being a keen biologist first, a metaphysician second, he believed the state should be understood as an organism with a purpose, in this case, to promote happiness, or eudaimonia. Of course, this is only a particular type of happiness, quintessentially that of philosophical contemplation, that the Greeks - or at least the philosophers! - valued most. But in this basic assumption, Aristotle’s theory of human society is actually fundamentally different from Socrates and Plato’s.
For Aristotle, society is a means to ensure that the social nature of people - in forming families, in forming friendships and equally in trying to rule and control others, is channelled away from the negative attributes of human beings - greed and cruelty - towards the positive aspects - love of truth and knowledge - those of what he classed misleadingly as ‘the rational animal’. Misleading, because, after all, any animal is rational to the extent that it takes decisions to obtain food or to preserve its life. (The Chinese sages instead defined humans as ‘moral animals’.) Certainly, rationality pursued as a philosophical venture remained only available to an aristocratic leisured few.
In other ways, too, Aristotle’s Politics strike a discordant note. He defined the state as a collection of a certain size of citizens participating in the judicial and political processes of the City. But the term ‘citizens’ was not to include many inhabitants of the city. He did not include slaves, nor (unlike Plato) women, nor yet those who worked for a living. ‘For some men,’ Aristotle wrote, ‘belong by nature to others’ and so should properly be either slaves or chattels.  
For Aristotle, liberty is fundamental for citizens - but it is a peculiar kind of liberty even for these privileged members of society. The state reserves the right to ensure efficient use of property, for its own advantage, and Aristotle agrees with Plato, that the production of children should be controlled to ensure the new citizens have ‘the best physique’. ( In Plato, it is put more generally so as to ‘improve on nature’. ) And, again like Plato, naturally, they will have to be educated in the manner determined by the state. ‘Public matters should be publicly managed; and we should not think that each of the citizens belongs to himself, but that they all belong to the State.’ Aristotle even produces a long list of ways in which the lives of citizens should be controlled. For the state is like the father in a well-regulated household: the children, (the citizens) ‘start with a natural affection and disposition to obey.


====Modal logic====
===The Laws of Thought===
Aristotle is also the creator of [[syllogism]]s with modalities ([[modal logic]], concerning the modes of [[truth]]. Aristotle introduced the qualification of 'necessary' and 'possible' premises.
Aristotle’s greatest achievement is generally supposed to have been his Laws of Thought - part of his attempt to put everyday language on a logical footing. Like many contemporary philosophers he regarded logic as providing the key to philosophical progress. The traditional ‘laws of thought’ are that:


===Science===
• whatever is, is (the law of identity);
Aristotelian discussions about science had only been qualitative, not quantitative. By the modern definition of the term, Aristotelian philosophy was not science, as this [[worldview]] did not attempt to probe how the world worked through experiment.
•  nothing can both be and not be (the law of non-contradiction); and
• everything must either be or not be (the law of excluded middle).


==Aristotle's metaphysics==
His ''Prior Analytics'' is the first attempt o create a system of formal deductive logic.
===Causality===
In ''[[Metaphysics]]'' and ''[[Posterior Analytics]]'', Aristotle argued that all causes of things are beginnings; that we have scientific knowledge when we know the cause; and that to know a thing's existence is to know the reason for its existence. He set the guidelines for all subsequent causal theories by specifying the number, nature, principles, elements, varieties, and order of causes as well as the modes of causation. According to Aristotle, causes fall into several groups, which amount to the ways in which the question 'why' may be answered; namely by reference to the matter or the ''substratum''; the essence, the pattern, the form, or the structure; the primary moving change or the agent and its action; the goal, the plan, the end, or the good. As a consequence, the four major kinds of causes are:


# The [[Material Cause]] is that from which a thing comes into existence (i.e., its parts, constituents, substratum or materials). This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts that comprise the whole system (the part-whole causation).
===Science===
# The [[Formal Cause]] tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis, or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (macrostructure) is the cause of its parts (the whole-part causation).
{|align="right" cellpadding="10" style="background:lightgray; width:35%; border: 1px solid #aaa; margin:20px; font-size: 93%; font-family: Gill Sans MT;"
# The [[Efficient Cause]] is that from which the change or the ending of the change begins. It identifies "what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed" and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. This covers the modern definitions of 'cause' as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs.
| A science, according to Aristotle, can be set out as an axiomatic system in which necessary first principles lead by inexorable inferences to all of the truths about the subject matter of the science...Scientific knowledge is therefore demonstrative; what we know scientifically is what we can derive, directly or indirectly, from first principles that do not themselves require proof...What, then, is the status of the first principles? They clearly cannot be known in the same way as the consequences derived from them, i.e., demonstratively, yet Aristotle is confident that they must be known—for how could knowledge be derived from what is not knowledge? They are, Aristotle tells us, grasped by the mind (Aristotle's term is ''nous'', usually translated as intuition or understanding). This way of putting the matter makes it seem as if an Aristotelian science is an entirely a priori enterprise in which reason alone grasps first principles and logic takes over from there to arrive at all of the truths of science...Aristotle does not think that this alone is the way a scientist goes about acquiring his knowledge, for in his own scientific treatises, he does not begin by announcing the first principles and deducing their consequences. Rather, he sets out the puzzles the science is trying to solve and the observations that have been made and the opinions that have been held about them. Perhaps he thinks of the axiomatic presentation as a kind of ideal that is possible only for a completed science and is appropriate for teaching it rather than for making discoveries in it. As for the acquisition of first principles, Aristotle appeals to what sounds somewhat like an inductive procedure. Beginning with the perception of particulars, which are "better known to us,' and moving through memory and experience, we arrive at knowledge of universals, which are "better known in themselves"...Aristotle's approach thus seems to combine features of both rationalism and empiricism.
# The [[Final Cause]] is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause or ''telos'' is the purpose that something serves, or that ''from which'' and ''to which'' the change is. This also covers modern ideas of mental causation involving such psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or motives, rational, irrational and ethical, that give purpose to behavior.
: &mdash;&nbsp;Cohen SM, Curd P, Reeve CDC<ref name=cohen2011> Cohen SM, Curd P, Reeve CDC. (2011) ''Readings in Ancient Greek Philosophy: From Thales to Aristotle''. Fourth Edition. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, ISBN 9781603844635; ISBN 9781603844628; Adobe PDF ebook ISBN 9781603845977. </ref>
 
|}
Additionally, things can be causes of one another, causing each other reciprocally, as hard work causes fitness and vice versa, although not in the same way or function, the one is as the beginning of change, the other as the goal. Thus Aristotle first suggested a reciprocal or circular causality as a relation of mutual dependence or action or influence of cause and effect. Also, Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of contrary effects, its presence and absence may result in different outcomes.
The ''Posterior Analytics'' attempts to use this to systematise scientific knowledge. In fact, about a quarter of Aristotle's writing seems to have been concerned with categorising nature, in particular animals. He describes the nature of space and time, and the different forms soul takes in different creatures. Some of his observations (such as that of how dolphins gave birth to their young) were careful and original, but equally certainly Aristotle has his fair share of foolish views, such as the influential but false doctrine that bodies fall to earth at speeds proportional to their mass, or the uninfluential but foolish claim that women had less teeth than men.
 
Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation and accidental (chance) causation. All causes, proper and incidental, can be spoken as potential or as actual, particular or generic. The same language refers to the effects of causes, so that generic effects are assigned to generic causes, particular effects to particular causes, operating causes to actual effects. Essentially, causality does not suggest a temporal relation between cause and effect.
 
All further investigations of causality will be consisting in imposing the favorite hierarchies on the order causes, like as final > efficient> material > formal ([[Thomas Aquinas]]), or in restricting all causality to the material and efficient causes or to the efficient causality (deterministic or chance) or just to regular sequences and correlations of natural phenomena (the natural sciences describing how things happen instead of explaining the whys and wherefores).
 
 
 
===Substance, potentiality, and actuality===
Aristotle examines the concept of [[substance]] (''ousia'') in his [[Metaphysics]], Book VII and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form. As he proceeds to the book VIII, he concludes that the matter of the substance is the [[substratum]] or the stuff of which is composed e.g. the matter of the house are the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the ''potential'' house. While the form of the substance, is the ''actual'' house, namely "covering for bodies and chattels" or any other [[differentia]]. The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form (Metaphysics VIII, 1043a 10-30).
 
With regard to change (''kinesis'') and its causes now, as he defines in his [[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]] and [[On Generation and Corruption]], he distinguishes the ''coming to be'' from
# ''growth and diminution'', (change in quantity)
# ''locomotion'', (change in space) and
# ''alteration'', (change in quality).  
 
The ''coming to be'' is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of [[potentiality]] (''dynamis'') and [[actuality]] (''entelecheia'') in association with the matter and the form.
 
Referring to [[potentiality]], is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if it is not prevented from something else. For example, a seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (''dynamei'') plant, and if is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either "act" (''poiein'') or "be acted upon" (''paschein''), as well as can be either innate or come by practice or learning. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate - being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise, acting).  
 
Referring now to [[actuality]], this is the fulfillment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (''telos'') is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that actuality is when the seed of the plant becomes a plant.
:"For that for the sake of which a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see." (Aristotle, ''Metaphysics'' IX 1050a 5-10).
 
In conclusion, the matter of the house is its potentiality and the form is its actuality. The [[Formal Cause]] (''aitia'') then of that change from potential to actual house, is the [[reason]] (''logos'') of the house builder and the [[Final Cause]] is the end, namely the house itself. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality.  
 
With this [[definition]] of the [[particular]] substance (matter and form) Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings; e.g., what is that makes the man one? Since, according to [[Plato]] there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same thing. (Aristotle, Metaphysics VIII 1045a-b).
 
== Aristotle's ethics ==
Although Aristotle wrote several works on [[ethics]], the major one was the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'', which is considered one of his greatest works; it discusses [[virtue]]s. The ten books which comprise it are based on notes from his lectures at the [[Lyceum]] and were either edited by or dedicated to his son, [[Nicomachus]]. Aristotle believed that ethical knowledge is not ''certain'' knowledge, like [[metaphysics]] and [[epistemology]], but ''general knowledge''. Also, as it is a practical discipline rather than a [[theory|theoretical]] one; he thought that to be "good", one could not simply study what virtue ''is''; one must actually do virtuous deeds. To do this, he had first to establish what was virtuous, and he began by determining that everything was done with some goal in mind and that goal is good. The ultimate goal he called the Highest Good.


Aristotle contended that happiness could not be found only in pleasure or only in fame and honor. He finally finds happiness "by ascertaining the specific function of man". But what is this function that will bring happiness? To determine this, Aristotle analyzed the soul and found it to have three parts: the Nutritive Soul (plants, animals and humans), the Perceptive Soul (animals and humans) and the Rational Soul (humans only). Thus, a human's function is to do what makes it human, to be good at what sets it apart from everything else: the ability to reason. A person that does this is the happiest because they are fulfilling their purpose or nature as found in the rational soul. Depending on how well they did this, Aristotle said people belonged to one of four categories: the Virtuous, the Continent, the Incontinent and the Vicious.
{{Image|Classical elements.png|left|250px|Fig. 1 The four Aristotelian elements and their interconversion}}


Aristotle believed that every ethical virtue is an intermediate condition between [[excess]] and [[deficiency]]. However, this does not mean that he believed in moral relativism; he considered some emotions (e.g., hate, envy, jealousy, spite.) and some actions (e.g., adultery, theft, murderas to be always wrong, regardless of circumstances. In the ''Nicomachean Ethics'', Aristotle often focused on how to find the mean between two extremes; for example; too much courage leads to ignorant choices, and too little would be cowardice. Aristotle says that finding this middle ground is essential to reaching eudemonia, the ultimate form of godlike consciousness. This middle ground is often referred to as The ''Golden Mean.'' Aristotle also wrote about justice in the ''Nicomachean Ethics'', defining ''General justice'' as a universal justice that can only exist in a perfect society, and ''Particular justice'' as where punishment is given out for a particular crime. Aristotle says an educated judge is needed to apply just decisions regarding any particular case. This is where we get the concept of he scales of justice, the blindfolded judge symbolizing blind justice, balancing the scales, weighing all the evidence and deliberating each particular case individually. Homonymy is an important theme in Aristotle’s justice because one form of justice can apply to one, while another would be best suited for a different person/case. Aristotle says that developing good habits can make a good human being and that practicing the use of The golden mean when applicable to virtues will allow a human being to live a healthy, happy life.
Following [[Empedocles]], Aristotle distinguishes four sub-lunar elements each with two basic properties (''qualitates symbolae'')
<div align = "center">
<table width="30%">
<tr> <td> <b>Earth</b> <td> dry <td> cold
<tr> <td> <b>Water</b> <td>    <td> cold <td> wet
<tr> <td> <b>Air </b> <td>    <td>      <td> wet <td> hot
<tr> <td> <b>Fire </b> <td>    <td>      <td>    <td> hot <td> dry
</tr></table>
</div>


== The loss of his works ==
He claims that all homogeneous materials are compounds of these four elements. All elements can be converted into each other, but most preferably the conversion is to an element that shares one of the four basic properties  (dry, wet, cold, hot) with the element to be converted, see Fig. 1. To the four earthly element Aristotle added a fifth heavenly element, the [[ether (physics)|Aether]].
Although we know that Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises ([[Cicero]] described his literary style as "a river of gold"), the originals have been lost. All that we have now are the literary notes of his pupils, which are often difficult to read (the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' is a good example). It is now believed that we have about one fifth of his original works.


Aristotle never published his books, only his dialogues. The story of the original manuscripts of his treatises is described by [[Strabo]] in his Geography and [[Plutarch]] in his "[[Parallel Lives]], Sulla": The manuscripts were left from Aristotle to [[Theophrastus]], from Theophrastus to [[Neleus of Scepsis]], from Neleus to his heirs. Their descendants sold them to [[Apellicon of Teos]]. When [[Lucius Cornelius Sulla]] occupied Athens in 86 BCE, he carried off the library of Appellicon to [[Rome]], where they were first published in 60 BCE from the grammarian [[Tyrranion of Amisus]] and then by philosopher [[Andronicus of Rhodes]].
===Ethics===
Aristotle's views on morality are set out in the ''Nicomachean'' and the ''Eudaemian'' Ethics. The ''Nicomachean Ethics'' is one of the most influential books of moral philosophy, including accounts of what the Greeks considered to be the great virtues, and Aristotle’s great souled man, who speaks with a deep voice and level utterance, and who is not unduly modest either, as well as reminding us wisely that “without friends, no one would choose to live, though he had all other goods”. The main idea in Aristotle's ethics is that the proper end of mankind is the pursuit of ''eudaimonia'' which is Greek for a very particular kind of ‘happiness’. ''Eudaimonia'' has three aspects: as well as mere pleasure, there is political honour,, and the rewards of contemplation. Quintessentially, of course, as philosophy.


== Bibliography ==
Other doctrines often attributed to Aristotle, notably the merit of fulfilling your ‘function’, of cultivating the ‘virtues’, (hence, 'virtue ethics') and of the ‘golden mean’ between two undesirable extremes are, of course, all much older. Indeed Plato puts the ideas forward much more cogently.
''Note: [[Bekker numbers]] are often used to uniquely identify passages of Aristotle. They are identified below where available.''
Nonetheless, one important difference between Aristotle and Plato is there in the ''Nicomachean Ethics'', where Aristotle starts with a survey of popular opinions on the subject of 'right and wrong', to find out how the terms are used, in the manner of a social; anthropologist. Plato makes very clear his contempt for such an approach. [[Thomas Hobbes]] said that it was this method that had led Aristotle astray, as by seeking to ground ethics in the 'appetites of men', he had chosen a measure by which (for Hobbes) correctly there is no law and no distinction between right and wrong. In fact, Hobbes considered Aristotle a great fool, protesting repeatedly the 'folly' of 'the Ancients.


=== Major works ===
==Influence==
The extant works of Aristotle are broken down according to the five categories in the ''[[Corpus Aristotelicum]]''. Some, such as the ''Athenaion Politeia'' or the fragments of other ''politeia'' are generally regarded as products of Aristotle's "school", compiled under his direction. Others, including ''On Colours'' may have been written by Aristotle's successors at the Lyceum, e.g., [[Theophrastus]] and [[Straton]]. Still others acquired Aristotle's name through similarities in doctrine or content, such as the ''De Plantis,'' possibly by [[Nicolaus of Damascus]]. A final category, omitted here, includes medieval [[palmistries]], [[astrological]] and [[magical]] texts whose connection to Aristotle is purely conjectural. Those that are seriously disputed are marked with an asterisk.
Aristotle represented an advanced paradigm at the time of his work. His epistemology contradicted his teacher Plato in a crucial manner. Both valued and emphasised reason and its use but Plato insisted that the most important truths, the objects of knowledge, must be attained through reason alone,


==== Logical writings ====
Aristotle on the other hand, emphasised observation, holding that the world and the mind were compatible in that understanding was possible. This may have been articulated as such earlier by someone else, but prior to Aristotle, there was a history of observation by the pre-socratic philosophers to substantiate understanding.<ref>[http://en.citizendium.org/wiki/History_of_astronomy#Pre-socratic_Astronomy Internal CZ Link to History of Astronomy]</ref> While this may seem trivial, even self evident now, this was a paramount step toward the development of science and it is a crucial aspect of any field in science, that we believe that we can know. And for Aristotle that knowing was achieved through observing.
* [[Organon]] (collected works on logic):
** (1a) [[Categories (Aristotle)|Categories]] (or ''Categoriae'')
** (16a) [[On Interpretation]] (or ''De Interpretatione'')
** (24a) [[Prior Analytics]] (or ''Analytica Priora'')
** (71a) [[Posterior Analytics]] (or ''Analytica Posteriora'')
** (100b) [[Topics (Aristotle)|Topics]] (or ''Topica'')
** (164a) [[On Sophistical Refutations]] (or ''De Sophisticis Elenchis'')


==== Physical and scientific writings ====
Most of Aristotle’s observations have been lost. His world was the world of Philip of Macedon and Alexander the Great. His association with the royal Macedonian house made it necessary to move around a great deal. In the years that followed his death, most of his works were lost and much of what remains are compilations made centuries later, collections of notes and original works. As the centuries continued, translations were made and then translations of those translations. In the end very little of his original work remains now, more than 2,300 years later
* (184a) [[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]] (or ''Physica'')
* (268a) [[On the Heavens]] (or ''De Caelo'')
* (314a) [[On Generation and Corruption]] (or ''De Generatione et Corruptione'')
* (338a) [[Meteorology (Aristotle)|Meteorology]] (or ''Meteorologica'')
* (391a) [[On the Cosmos]] (or ''De Mundo'', or ''On the Universe'') *
* (402a) [[On the Soul]] (or ''De Anima'')
* (436a) [[Little Physical Treatises]] (or ''Parva Naturalia''):
** [[On Sense and the Sensible]] (or ''De Sensu et Sensibilibus'')
** [[On Memory and Reminiscence]] (or ''De Memoria et Reminiscentia'')
** [[On Sleep and Sleeplessness]] (or ''De Somno et Vigilia'')
** [[On Dreams]] (or ''De Insomniis'') *
** [[On Prophesying by Dreams]] (or ''De Divinatione per Somnum'')
** [[On Longevity and Shortness of Life]] (or ''De Longitudine et Brevitate Vitae'')
** [[On Youth and Old Age]] (On Life and Death) (or ''De Juventute et Senectute'', ''De Vita et Morte'')
** [[On Breathing]] (or ''De Respiratione'')
* (481a) [[On Breath]] (or ''De Spiritu'') *
* (486a) [[History of Animals]] (or ''Historia Animalium'', or ''On the History of Animals'', or ''Description of Animals'')
* (639a) [[On the Parts of Animals]] (or ''De Partibus Animalium'')
* (698a) [[On the Gait of Animals]] (or ''De Motu Animalium'', or ''On the Movement of Animals'')
* (704a) [[On the Progression of Animals]] (or ''De Incessu Animalium'')
* (715a) [[On the Generation of Animals]] (or ''De Generatione Animalium'')
* (791a) [[On Colours]] (or ''De Coloribus'') *
* (800a) ''[[De audibilibus]]''
* (805a) [[Physiognomics]] (or ''Physiognomonica'') *
* [[On Plants]] (or ''De Plantis'') *
* (830a) [[On Marvellous Things Heard]] (or ''Mirabilibus Auscultationibus'', or ''On Things Heard'') *
* (847a) [[Mechanical Problems]] (or ''Mechanica'') *
* (859a) [[Problems (Aristotle)|Problems]] (or ''Problemata'') *
* (968a) [[On Indivisible Lines]] (or ''De Lineis Insecabilibus'') *
* (973a) [[Situations and Names of Winds]] (or ''Ventorum Situs'') *
* (974a) [[On Melissus, Xenophanes and Gorgias]] (or ''MXG'') * The section On Xenophanes starts at 977a13, the section On Gorgias starts at 979a11.


==== Metaphysical writings ====
So, while his observations and his deductions for those observations were very important in the development of science that was to come later, it is fragmented and what remains is full of errors. He did however bestow the early seeds of systematic investigation into natural phenomena and to that extent can be credited at least as a midwife at the birth of empirical science if not actually the founder. It is a tragic irony that his observations and opinions were to stifle the very thing he pursued for so many years.
* (980a) [[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]] (or ''Metaphysica'')


==== Ethical writings ====
Aristotle treated knowledge as common property, not to be held in secret. He worked in the company of others and readily spoke and wrote of this thoughts. His attitude in this prefigures one of the foundations of modern science in that he believed that one could not claim to know a subject unless capable and willing to transmit that knowledge to others. This attitude of openness was often lacking in some of the greatest thinkers of the 15th through the 17th century and was to cause no end of grief. Even up to this day the actual credit for some of the primary advances in science are still being debated due to a lack of cooperation and openness practiced by Artistotle nearly 2,000 years earlier.
* (1094a) [[Nicomachean Ethics]] (or ''Ethica Nicomachea'', or ''The Ethics'')
* (1181a) [[Great Ethics]] (or ''Magna Moralia'') *
* (1214a) [[Eudemian Ethics]] (or ''Ethica Eudemia'')
* (1249a) [[Virtues and Vices]] (or ''De Virtutibus et Vitiis Libellus'', ''Libellus de virtutibus'') *
* (1252a) [[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]] (or ''Politica'')
* (1343a) [[Economics (Aristotle)|Economics]] (or ''Oeconomica'')


==== Aesthetic writings ====
Another of his contributions, Aristotle also made the divisions in knowledge we have today, theology and physics and math, language, ethics and politics are all distinct separate fields. This too would have far reaching implications.
* (1354a) [[Rhetoric (Aristotle)|Rhetoric]] (or ''Ars Rhetorica'', or ''The Art of Rhetoric'' or ''Treatise on Rhetoric'')
* [[Rhetoric to Alexander]] (or ''Rhetorica ad Alexandrum'') *
* (1447a) [[Poetics]] (or ''Ars Poetica''); (first book only; second book on Comedy since lost)


==== A work outside the ''Corpus Aristotelicum'' ====
One of the most enduring works on the subject of cosmology was his ''On the heavens'' written about 350 BCE Until it was seriously challenged in the early 16th century by [[Copernicus]], amongst others, it was the considered authority on [[Cosmology|cosmology]]. He posited the nature of substance, the nature and manner of movement, the nature of the heavens and its eternal existence.
* The [[Constitution of the Athenians]] (or ''Athenaion Politeia'', or ''The Athenian Constitution'')


=== Specific editions===
How much of what we have that is attributed to him is in fact what he said or wrote--regardless of whether he was the originator or he learned form others--or was simply added to his writings after his death is debatable. One of the standard works on Aristotle was that of W. W. Jaeger (1888-1961). His interpretations of Aristotles works included his opinions about what was added later. Jeager's summations in the classic ''Artistotle'' (1948) still receive critical analysis
* [[Princeton University]] Press: ''The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation'' (2 Volume Set; Bollingen Series, Vol. LXXI, No. 2), edited by [[Jonathan Barnes]] ISBN 0-691-09950-2 (The most complete recent translation of Aristotle's extant works)
* [[Oxford University Press]]: ''Clarendon Aristotle Series''. [http://www.oup.com/us/catalog/general/series/ClarendonAristotleSeries/?view=usa Scholarly edition]
* [[Harvard University]] Press: ''[[Loeb Classical Library#Aristotle|Loeb Classical Library]]'' (hardbound; publishes in Greek, with English translations on facing pages)
* [[Oxford Classical Texts]] (hardbound; Greek only)


<ref>[http://phyun5.ucr.edu/~wudka/Physics7/Notes_www/node35.html Aristotelian Cosmology] Wudka, Jose (1998) ''Relativity and Cosmology'', Physics Dept. University of California, Riverside; [http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/heavens.mb.txt On the Heavens] Stock, J.L (trans); [http://users.ox.ac.uk/~worc0337/authors/aristotle.html Aristotle Life and Work] King, Peter J.,  Pembroke College, Oxford University; [http://www-gap.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Biographies/Aristotle.html Aristotle Biography] O'Connor, John J.  and Robertson, Edmund F. (1999). ''MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive'', School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland; William M. Calder III (ed.), ''Werner Jaeger Reconsidered''. Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1992. Illinois Classical Studies; [http://classics.mit.edu//Aristotle/metaphysics.1.i.html Translated by W. D. Ross] Internet Classics Archive, Massachusetts Institute of Technology</ref>


===Contemporary Aristotelians===


==Notes==
Despite that during the early modern period Aristotle's ideas fell out of fashion due to the emergence of a new paradigm based on [[Descartes]], [[Locke]], and [[Kant]], many contemporary scholars have sought to revive Aristotle's legacy in many fields. In ethics and politics, [[Ayn Rand]], [[Philippa Foot]], and [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] are among these thinkers.
<references/>


==See also==
==Criticism of Aristotle==
*[[Aristotelian view of God]]
Aristotle is generally counted as one of the 'great philosophers'. However, during his lifetime and for many years afterwards, his reputation was rather less golden. Indeed, the renowned 'sceptic', Timon of Philus, sneered at "the sad chattering of the empty Aristotle" while Theocritus of Chios wrote a rather unkind epigram on him which runs:
*[[Aristotelian theory of gravity]]
<blockquote>
*[[Philia]]
The empty-headed Aristotle rais'd
*[[Phronesis]]
This empty tomb to Hermias the Eunuch,
*[[Potentiality and actuality (Aristotle)]]
The ancient slave of the ill-us'd Eubulus.
(Who for his monstrous appetite, preferred
The Bosphorus to Academia's groves.)
</blockquote>


==External links==
In the Nineteenth Century,  the scientist, John Tyndall, complained that Aristotle's statements were most accepted when they were most incorrect, whilst in the Twentieth, Karl Popper accused Aristotle of having held up the development of thought itself. <ref> Philosophical Tales, by Martin Cohen, Blackwell 2008 p14 </ref>
* {{MacTutorBio|id=Aristotle}}
*[http://www.non-contradiction.com/ An extensive collection of Aristotle's philosophy and works, including lesser known texts]
*[http://www.threescholars.com/  Help with Aristotle essays]
*{{gutenberg author | id=Aristotle | name=Aristotle}}
*[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-biology/ Biology]" -- by James Lennox.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-causality/ Causality]" -- by Andrea Falcon.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-ethics/ Ethics]" -- by Richard Kraut.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-logic/ Logic]" -- by Robin Smith.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-mathematics/ Mathematics]" -- by Henry Mendell.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ Metaphysics]" -- by S. Marc Cohen.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-natphil/ Philosophy of Nature]" -- Istvan Bodnar.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-politics/ Political Theory]" -- by Fred Miller.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-psychology/ Psychology]" -- by Christopher Shields.
**"[http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/aristotle-rhetoric/ Rhetoric]" -- by Cristof Rapp.
*[http://www.ellopos.net/blog/?p=44 Aristotle OnLine Resources & Anthology of his works]
*[[Catholic Encyclopedia]]: "[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/01713a.htm Aristotle]" &mdash; by William Turner.
*Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "[http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/a/aristotl.htm  Aristotle]".
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/Main/Philosophers.aspx?PhilCode=Aris Aristotle section at EpistemeLinks]
*[http://Aristotle.thefreelibrary.com/ A brief biography and e-texts presented one chapter at a time]
*[http://uk.arxiv.org/abs/physics/0505172 Aristotle and Indian logic]
*[http://www.greektexts.com/library/Aristotle/index.html Large collection of Aristotle's texts, presented page by page]
*[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/01713a.htm Source of most of the Biography and Methodology sections, as well as more overview]
* [http://www.clown-enfant.com/leclown/eng/quizz2.htm Test : Are you Aristotelian? (cf. ''Poetics'')]
* [http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/320/4causes.htm "The Four Causes", Lecture by S. Marc Cohen]]


*{{planetmath|id=5840|title=Aristotle}}
<blockquote>
The development of thought since Aristotle, could, I think, be summed up by saying that every discipline, as long as it used the Aristotelian method of definition, has remained arrested in a  state of empty verbiage and barren scholasticism, and that the degree to which the various sciences have been able to make any progress depended on the degree to which they have been able to get rid of this essentialist method. (This is why so much of our "social science" still belongs to the Middle Ages).<ref> K. R. Popper, ''The open society and its enemies. Vol. 2. Hegel and Marx.''
London: Routledge, (1945). p. 9 </ref>
</blockquote>


[[Category:Classics Workgroup]]
===Notes===
[[Category:History Workgroup]]
{{reflist|2}}[[Category:Suggestion Bot Tag]]
[[Category:Philosophy Workgroup]]
[[Category:CZ Live]]

Latest revision as of 16:00, 12 July 2024

This article is developing and not approved.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
Works [?]
 
This editable Main Article is under development and subject to a disclaimer.
© Giovanni Dall'Orto
A marble bust of Aristotle.

Aristotle (Ancient Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης, Aristotélēs), a Greek philosopher of the fourth century BCE, was born just in time to know Plato, another influential philosopher, and worked on many diverse subjects with unusual taxonomical zeal.

Aristotle was particularly interested in observing nature and his writings on biology were much admired by Charles Darwin amongst others. Throughout the Middle Ages, no other thinker had as great an influence as Aristotle, and he merited in the thirteenth century alone some five separate Papal bans. Today, Aristotle's legacy remains in many fields of endeavour and he is usually considered one of the great foundational figures of both philosophy and natural science.

Early years

(PD) Image: West Point Military Academy
Greece at the time of Aristotle (Chalcidic Peninsula lays between Thrace and Macedonia at the north-west edge of the Aegean Sea.) Source: U.S.M.A.

Born in 384 BCE in Stagirus (alternately Stagira or Stageirus), a small town in northern Greece on the Chalcidic Peninsula, to Nicomachus, a medical doctor, and Phaestis, his mother, Aristotle’s family was probably native to that area.

Traditionally a son followed his father’s profession or trade. However, Nicomachus died when Aristotle was a boy. Prior to that death, there is reason to believe that his father’s influence was significant. At the time, patients did not got to doctors, doctors went their patients. It is not unreasonable to think Aristotle accompanied his father on his travels.

Nicomachus found work more to his preferences in the neighboring state of Macedonia and he was eventually appointed personal physician to Amyntas III, the king of Macedonia, in the capitol, Pella. This was the King Amyntas whose son Philip successfully united a number of the Greek city states after defending Macedonia, and he in turn was the father of Alexander, The Great. Aristotle was almost the exact age as Philip and it is likely that they were acquainted if not actually friends. Later in life Philip was to support some of Aristotle’s ambitions, if only for a time, indicating that they agreed on some things and enjoyed some measure of trust.

Nicomachus died about the time Aristotle was 10 years old. As a consequence he did not become a physician. Although it is not absolutely clear from the evidence we have, it would also seem that his mother Phaestis, died while Aristotle was young

Aristotle’s future was then in the hands of a guardian, Proxenus of Atarneus, who might have been an uncle or a family friend. Proxenus was a teacher of Greek, rhetoric, and poetry, which presumably would have rounded out the teaching in biological topics Aristotle had received from his father. Aristotle’s prose written later in life was of such quality that it seems reasonable to think he was also taught this subject when he was young.[1][2]

Plato's Academy

In 367, at the age of 17, he was sent to Athens where he entered Plato’s Academy and remained there for twenty years. It is not clear why Aristotle went to Athens; perhaps he had read Plato’s dialogues while in Stagira and wanted to study with him in particular or maybe Athens was simply the place to study at the time. During those twenty years, Aristotle was not simply a pupil; he carried out independent studies in natural science, and led lectures especially on the subject of rhetoric. Plato died in 347 and leadership of the Academy was passed on to his nephew Speusippus, who best represented the teachings of Plato. While Plato lived, Aristotle was a loyal member of the Academy; however even then, Aristotle’s thoughts on important points began to diverge from Platonism. Perhaps due to his growing dissatisfaction with the curriculum of the Academy or to anti-Macedonian feeling at Athens due to political unrest, Aristotle accepted an invitation from Hermeias, a former fellow-student in the Academy turned ruler of Atarneus and Assos, on the coast of Asia minor.

Years at Atarneus

He remained in Atarneus for three years and married Pythias, niece of Hermeias, who bore him a daughter of the same name. After the death of his first wife, his second wife Herpyllis, a native to Stagira, bore him a son, Nicomachus, after whom the Nicomachean Ethics were named. At the end of three years, Aristotle moved to Mitylene, a neighboring island of Lesbos. Aristotle’s works suggest that he devoted part of his time in the Aegean to the study of marine biology.

Relocating to Pella

In 343, Philip of Macedon, in succession to his father Amyntas, invited Aristotle to undertake the education of his thirteen year old son, Alexander, who later would become Alexander the Great. Little to nothing is known about the education of Alexander but it is probably during this time that Aristotle turned his attention to political subjects. In 340, Alexander was appointed regent for his father and his pupillage ended. Subsequently, Aristotle may have settled in Stagira.

Death of Philip and Establishing the Lyceum

In 335, soon after Philip’s assassination, Aristotle returned to Athens and though the Academy flourished under new leadership, he preferred to set up his own school called the Lyceum. Every morning at the Lyceum, Aristotle and his students discussed the more abstruse philosophical matters such as logic, physics and metaphysics and in the afternoon and evenings held lectures/discussions in more popular matters such as rhetoric and politics. Shortly after the death of Alexander the Great in 323, anti-Macedonian feelings swept over Athens and Aristotle, once again, left Athens and retired to Chalcis, where his mother’s family had estates. Soon after, in 322, he died.[3][4]

The works of Aristotle

Please refer to this page’s catalog for a complete list of Aristotle’s works, and to the subpage on the spurious works of Aristotle.

Though much of Aristotle’s thought is historically interesting, it is also fascinating because it is a comprehensive picture of the world that differs, in some ways dramatically, from that of modern people. The works of Aristotle, however, can be daunting to the uninitiated.

Unlike the carefully presented and highly literary works of Plato, the works of Aristotle tend to be terse and pithy, and to an extreme extent. In fact, the works of Aristotle which survive to the present day seem to be something like lecture notes.[5] In addition to the prose style of Aristotle’s extant works, his texts are also made difficult by their frequently piecemeal nature. A comparison with Plato is again useful. Plato’s works are made to be read by an individual reader, and are generally self-contained. Aristotle’s works, as lecture notes, refer only briefly to important concepts that are not strictly relevant to the subject at hand. For example, much of his work is underlain by his conviction that particulars are ontologically prior to universals, but this idea is only explained at length in a couple of places. It’s worth observing that Aristotle, as a lecturer, would have been able to leave the topic at hand and explain any important ideas his listeners were unfamiliar with.

It is also important not to underestimate the difficulties that Aristotle’s language creates. Aristotle wrote in Ancient Greek, but it is not a Greek which translates easily to normal-sounding English. Aristotle makes liberal use of technical terms. For example, ‘form’ and ‘knowledge’ in English are each the best translation for three separate Greek words which Aristotle uses with different shades of meaning. He does not, however, use these terms consistently.

The style and organization of his works are not always negatives. Aristotle is made easier reading by the fact that his works frequently follow a predictable form. He often begins one of his investigations by stating the conclusions of earlier thinkers: frequently Plato, but other thinkers as well. [6] Then, he moves to a consideration of the problems, or aporiai, with a given idea, and he finally states his opinion-- before moving to a discussion of the problems with his opinion! (It can be helpful for the reader to highlight, underline, or otherwise mark the proposition Aristotle is espousing.)

Ideas, method and achievements [7]

Neither Aristotle nor the other Greek philosophers made any distinction between scientific and philosophical investigations. Aristotle was particularly interested in observing nature and his biology was much admired by Darwin amongst others. Aristotle influenced subsequent studies by his view that organisms had a function, were striving towards some purposeful end, and that nature is not haphazard. If plant shoots are observed to bend towards the light they are ‘seeking the light’. The function of mankind is, he suggests, to reason, as this is what people are better at than any other member of the animal kingdom - ‘Man is a rational animal’. This approach is in contrast to that of today's biologist or scientist who try to explain things by reference to ‘mechanisms’.

Political ideas

Aristotle marks the watershed in Greek philosophy, born fifteen years after the execution of Socrates in 399 B.C.E, studying at the Academy in Athens under Plato until B.C.E 347. Although he had hoped to become Plato's successor, in fact Aristotle's approach was was out of favour with the mathematicians of the time, and Plato's nephew, Speussippus took over instead. After this Aristotle left Greece for Asia Minor where for the next five years he concentrated on developing his philosophy and biology. He then returned to Macedonia to be tutor to the future Alexander the Great, but there is little evidence of him influencing his pupil and indeed Aristotle seems to have been largely oblivious to the social and geo-political changes that were already making his approach to politics largely irrelevant.

Indeed, even whilst Aristotle was teaching about the polis in the Lyceum, Alexander was already planning an empire in which he would rule the whole of Greece and Persia, in the process producing a new society in which both Greeks and barbarians would become, as Plutarch later put it, ‘one flock on a common pasture’ feeding under one law. In fact, whilst Aristotle wrote on the case of the 'polis', for almost two millennia the area was to see no city states, but instead a succession of empires. The rule of Macedonia, of Rome, and of Charlemagne came and went, with Aristotle not even so much as a footnote. Yet for much of this time, Aristotle was widely studied in the Islamic world, where he was hailed as 'the wise man' and his texts were carefully preserved. In the Middle Ages his ideas were 'rediscovered' by St Thomas Aquinas and, especially given the effective marriage of the Catholic Church with the state, became highly influential.

Aristotle was similarly concerned at the fractious nature of the Greek city states in his time, the fourth century B.C.E. The states were small, but that did not stop them continually splitting into factions that fought amongst themselves. A whole book of Aristotle’s political theory is devoted to this problem. And Aristotle shared Plato's aversion to tyranny, warning that under such government, all citizens would be constantly on view, and a secret police ‘like the female spies employed at Syracuse, or the eavesdroppers sent by the tyrant Hiero to all social gatherings’ would be employed to sow fear and distrust. For these are the essential and characteristic hallmarks of tyrants.

Aristotle sees the origin of the state differently from Plato, stating explicitly that ‘a State is not a sharing of a locality for the purpose of preventing mutual harm and promoting trade.’ True to his being a keen biologist first, a metaphysician second, he believed the state should be understood as an organism with a purpose, in this case, to promote happiness, or eudaimonia. Of course, this is only a particular type of happiness, quintessentially that of philosophical contemplation, that the Greeks - or at least the philosophers! - valued most. But in this basic assumption, Aristotle’s theory of human society is actually fundamentally different from Socrates and Plato’s.

For Aristotle, society is a means to ensure that the social nature of people - in forming families, in forming friendships and equally in trying to rule and control others, is channelled away from the negative attributes of human beings - greed and cruelty - towards the positive aspects - love of truth and knowledge - those of what he classed misleadingly as ‘the rational animal’. Misleading, because, after all, any animal is rational to the extent that it takes decisions to obtain food or to preserve its life. (The Chinese sages instead defined humans as ‘moral animals’.) Certainly, rationality pursued as a philosophical venture remained only available to an aristocratic leisured few.

In other ways, too, Aristotle’s Politics strike a discordant note. He defined the state as a collection of a certain size of citizens participating in the judicial and political processes of the City. But the term ‘citizens’ was not to include many inhabitants of the city. He did not include slaves, nor (unlike Plato) women, nor yet those who worked for a living. ‘For some men,’ Aristotle wrote, ‘belong by nature to others’ and so should properly be either slaves or chattels.

For Aristotle, liberty is fundamental for citizens - but it is a peculiar kind of liberty even for these privileged members of society. The state reserves the right to ensure efficient use of property, for its own advantage, and Aristotle agrees with Plato, that the production of children should be controlled to ensure the new citizens have ‘the best physique’. ( In Plato, it is put more generally so as to ‘improve on nature’. ) And, again like Plato, naturally, they will have to be educated in the manner determined by the state. ‘Public matters should be publicly managed; and we should not think that each of the citizens belongs to himself, but that they all belong to the State.’ Aristotle even produces a long list of ways in which the lives of citizens should be controlled. For the state is like the father in a well-regulated household: the children, (the citizens) ‘start with a natural affection and disposition to obey.’

The Laws of Thought

Aristotle’s greatest achievement is generally supposed to have been his Laws of Thought - part of his attempt to put everyday language on a logical footing. Like many contemporary philosophers he regarded logic as providing the key to philosophical progress. The traditional ‘laws of thought’ are that:

• whatever is, is (the law of identity); • nothing can both be and not be (the law of non-contradiction); and • everything must either be or not be (the law of excluded middle).

His Prior Analytics is the first attempt o create a system of formal deductive logic.

Science

A science, according to Aristotle, can be set out as an axiomatic system in which necessary first principles lead by inexorable inferences to all of the truths about the subject matter of the science...Scientific knowledge is therefore demonstrative; what we know scientifically is what we can derive, directly or indirectly, from first principles that do not themselves require proof...What, then, is the status of the first principles? They clearly cannot be known in the same way as the consequences derived from them, i.e., demonstratively, yet Aristotle is confident that they must be known—for how could knowledge be derived from what is not knowledge? They are, Aristotle tells us, grasped by the mind (Aristotle's term is nous, usually translated as intuition or understanding). This way of putting the matter makes it seem as if an Aristotelian science is an entirely a priori enterprise in which reason alone grasps first principles and logic takes over from there to arrive at all of the truths of science...Aristotle does not think that this alone is the way a scientist goes about acquiring his knowledge, for in his own scientific treatises, he does not begin by announcing the first principles and deducing their consequences. Rather, he sets out the puzzles the science is trying to solve and the observations that have been made and the opinions that have been held about them. Perhaps he thinks of the axiomatic presentation as a kind of ideal that is possible only for a completed science and is appropriate for teaching it rather than for making discoveries in it. As for the acquisition of first principles, Aristotle appeals to what sounds somewhat like an inductive procedure. Beginning with the perception of particulars, which are "better known to us,' and moving through memory and experience, we arrive at knowledge of universals, which are "better known in themselves"...Aristotle's approach thus seems to combine features of both rationalism and empiricism.
— Cohen SM, Curd P, Reeve CDC[8]

The Posterior Analytics attempts to use this to systematise scientific knowledge. In fact, about a quarter of Aristotle's writing seems to have been concerned with categorising nature, in particular animals. He describes the nature of space and time, and the different forms soul takes in different creatures. Some of his observations (such as that of how dolphins gave birth to their young) were careful and original, but equally certainly Aristotle has his fair share of foolish views, such as the influential but false doctrine that bodies fall to earth at speeds proportional to their mass, or the uninfluential but foolish claim that women had less teeth than men.

CC Image
Fig. 1 The four Aristotelian elements and their interconversion

Following Empedocles, Aristotle distinguishes four sub-lunar elements each with two basic properties (qualitates symbolae)

Earth dry cold
Water cold wet
Air wet hot
Fire hot dry

He claims that all homogeneous materials are compounds of these four elements. All elements can be converted into each other, but most preferably the conversion is to an element that shares one of the four basic properties (dry, wet, cold, hot) with the element to be converted, see Fig. 1. To the four earthly element Aristotle added a fifth heavenly element, the Aether.

Ethics

Aristotle's views on morality are set out in the Nicomachean and the Eudaemian Ethics. The Nicomachean Ethics is one of the most influential books of moral philosophy, including accounts of what the Greeks considered to be the great virtues, and Aristotle’s great souled man, who speaks with a deep voice and level utterance, and who is not unduly modest either, as well as reminding us wisely that “without friends, no one would choose to live, though he had all other goods”. The main idea in Aristotle's ethics is that the proper end of mankind is the pursuit of eudaimonia which is Greek for a very particular kind of ‘happiness’. Eudaimonia has three aspects: as well as mere pleasure, there is political honour,, and the rewards of contemplation. Quintessentially, of course, as philosophy.

Other doctrines often attributed to Aristotle, notably the merit of fulfilling your ‘function’, of cultivating the ‘virtues’, (hence, 'virtue ethics') and of the ‘golden mean’ between two undesirable extremes are, of course, all much older. Indeed Plato puts the ideas forward much more cogently.

Nonetheless, one important difference between Aristotle and Plato is there in the Nicomachean Ethics, where Aristotle starts with a survey of popular opinions on the subject of 'right and wrong', to find out how the terms are used, in the manner of a social; anthropologist. Plato makes very clear his contempt for such an approach. Thomas Hobbes said that it was this method that had led Aristotle astray, as by seeking to ground ethics in the 'appetites of men', he had chosen a measure by which (for Hobbes) correctly there is no law and no distinction between right and wrong. In fact, Hobbes considered Aristotle a great fool, protesting repeatedly the 'folly' of 'the Ancients.

Influence

Aristotle represented an advanced paradigm at the time of his work. His epistemology contradicted his teacher Plato in a crucial manner. Both valued and emphasised reason and its use but Plato insisted that the most important truths, the objects of knowledge, must be attained through reason alone,

Aristotle on the other hand, emphasised observation, holding that the world and the mind were compatible in that understanding was possible. This may have been articulated as such earlier by someone else, but prior to Aristotle, there was a history of observation by the pre-socratic philosophers to substantiate understanding.[9] While this may seem trivial, even self evident now, this was a paramount step toward the development of science and it is a crucial aspect of any field in science, that we believe that we can know. And for Aristotle that knowing was achieved through observing.

Most of Aristotle’s observations have been lost. His world was the world of Philip of Macedon and Alexander the Great. His association with the royal Macedonian house made it necessary to move around a great deal. In the years that followed his death, most of his works were lost and much of what remains are compilations made centuries later, collections of notes and original works. As the centuries continued, translations were made and then translations of those translations. In the end very little of his original work remains now, more than 2,300 years later

So, while his observations and his deductions for those observations were very important in the development of science that was to come later, it is fragmented and what remains is full of errors. He did however bestow the early seeds of systematic investigation into natural phenomena and to that extent can be credited at least as a midwife at the birth of empirical science if not actually the founder. It is a tragic irony that his observations and opinions were to stifle the very thing he pursued for so many years.

Aristotle treated knowledge as common property, not to be held in secret. He worked in the company of others and readily spoke and wrote of this thoughts. His attitude in this prefigures one of the foundations of modern science in that he believed that one could not claim to know a subject unless capable and willing to transmit that knowledge to others. This attitude of openness was often lacking in some of the greatest thinkers of the 15th through the 17th century and was to cause no end of grief. Even up to this day the actual credit for some of the primary advances in science are still being debated due to a lack of cooperation and openness practiced by Artistotle nearly 2,000 years earlier.

Another of his contributions, Aristotle also made the divisions in knowledge we have today, theology and physics and math, language, ethics and politics are all distinct separate fields. This too would have far reaching implications.

One of the most enduring works on the subject of cosmology was his On the heavens written about 350 BCE Until it was seriously challenged in the early 16th century by Copernicus, amongst others, it was the considered authority on cosmology. He posited the nature of substance, the nature and manner of movement, the nature of the heavens and its eternal existence.

How much of what we have that is attributed to him is in fact what he said or wrote--regardless of whether he was the originator or he learned form others--or was simply added to his writings after his death is debatable. One of the standard works on Aristotle was that of W. W. Jaeger (1888-1961). His interpretations of Aristotles works included his opinions about what was added later. Jeager's summations in the classic Artistotle (1948) still receive critical analysis

[10]

Contemporary Aristotelians

Despite that during the early modern period Aristotle's ideas fell out of fashion due to the emergence of a new paradigm based on Descartes, Locke, and Kant, many contemporary scholars have sought to revive Aristotle's legacy in many fields. In ethics and politics, Ayn Rand, Philippa Foot, and Alasdair MacIntyre are among these thinkers.

Criticism of Aristotle

Aristotle is generally counted as one of the 'great philosophers'. However, during his lifetime and for many years afterwards, his reputation was rather less golden. Indeed, the renowned 'sceptic', Timon of Philus, sneered at "the sad chattering of the empty Aristotle" while Theocritus of Chios wrote a rather unkind epigram on him which runs:

The empty-headed Aristotle rais'd This empty tomb to Hermias the Eunuch, The ancient slave of the ill-us'd Eubulus. (Who for his monstrous appetite, preferred The Bosphorus to Academia's groves.)

In the Nineteenth Century, the scientist, John Tyndall, complained that Aristotle's statements were most accepted when they were most incorrect, whilst in the Twentieth, Karl Popper accused Aristotle of having held up the development of thought itself. [11]

The development of thought since Aristotle, could, I think, be summed up by saying that every discipline, as long as it used the Aristotelian method of definition, has remained arrested in a state of empty verbiage and barren scholasticism, and that the degree to which the various sciences have been able to make any progress depended on the degree to which they have been able to get rid of this essentialist method. (This is why so much of our "social science" still belongs to the Middle Ages).[12]

Notes

  1. Aristotle Life and Work King, Peter J., Pembroke College, Oxford University
  2. Aristotle Biography O'Connor, John J. and Robertson, Edmund F. (1999). MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  3. Ross, D. Aristotle. Routledge Press, 2004. 336 pp.
  4. Barnes, J. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge University Press, 1995. 404 pp.
  5. p. 3, Barnes
  6. This is connected with his valuation of ‘reasonable opinions.’ Cf. the discussion at Barnes, 15ff.
  7. 'A large part of an early version of this section was taken from the entry on Aristotle in 'Essentials of Philosophy and Ethics', edited by Martin Cohen, (Hodder Arnold 2006) and donated to the Citizendium by the author.
  8. Cohen SM, Curd P, Reeve CDC. (2011) Readings in Ancient Greek Philosophy: From Thales to Aristotle. Fourth Edition. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, ISBN 9781603844635; ISBN 9781603844628; Adobe PDF ebook ISBN 9781603845977.
  9. Internal CZ Link to History of Astronomy
  10. Aristotelian Cosmology Wudka, Jose (1998) Relativity and Cosmology, Physics Dept. University of California, Riverside; On the Heavens Stock, J.L (trans); Aristotle Life and Work King, Peter J., Pembroke College, Oxford University; Aristotle Biography O'Connor, John J. and Robertson, Edmund F. (1999). MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland; William M. Calder III (ed.), Werner Jaeger Reconsidered. Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1992. Illinois Classical Studies; Translated by W. D. Ross Internet Classics Archive, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  11. Philosophical Tales, by Martin Cohen, Blackwell 2008 p14
  12. K. R. Popper, The open society and its enemies. Vol. 2. Hegel and Marx. London: Routledge, (1945). p. 9