Natural selection: Difference between revisions
imported>DavidGoodman No edit summary |
imported>DavidGoodman (oveerdominence) |
||
Line 3: | Line 3: | ||
'''Natural selection''' is the biological theory that explains why living creatures seem to match their environmental [[niche]]s so well. Natural selection is a long term process underlies the "fit" between living creatures and their habitat, and accounts for the presence of drought tolerant plants in the desert and moisture-loving plants in the rain forest, heavily furred mammals are in the colder climates and lightly furred mammals in the warmer climes, XXXX and XXX. . The ''result'' of natural selection is change in the characteristics of species of plants, animals, and other organisms through the generations, to the creation of new species, and their further evolution. | '''Natural selection''' is the biological theory that explains why living creatures seem to match their environmental [[niche]]s so well. Natural selection is a long term process underlies the "fit" between living creatures and their habitat, and accounts for the presence of drought tolerant plants in the desert and moisture-loving plants in the rain forest, heavily furred mammals are in the colder climates and lightly furred mammals in the warmer climes, XXXX and XXX. . The ''result'' of natural selection is change in the characteristics of species of plants, animals, and other organisms through the generations, to the creation of new species, and their further evolution. | ||
The theory of natural selection, like all theories, makes certain assumptions. First, there is the premise that there is some variety between the individual examples of any particular kind of living thing. Second, there is the premise that at least some of those variations are features that can be inherited by the offspring of the individuals that possess them. Thirdly, there is the assumption that in any given situation, some characteristics make survival of that individual more likely, whereas other characteristics make that survival less likely. Finally, natural selection depends on the premise that there are variable characteristics that also serve to make reproduction of an individual more or less likely. Given all these assumptions, the theory of natural selection predicts that living things with heritable features that bestow ''survival advantages'' for an individual, | The theory of natural selection, like all theories, makes certain assumptions. First, there is the premise that there is some variety between the individual examples of any particular kind of living thing. Second, there is the premise that at least some of those variations are features that can be inherited by the offspring of the individuals that possess them. Thirdly, there is the assumption that in any given situation, some characteristics make survival of that individual more likely, whereas other characteristics make that survival less likely. Finally, natural selection depends on the premise that there are variable characteristics that also serve to make reproduction of an individual more or less likely. Given all these assumptions, the theory of natural selection predicts that living things with heritable features that bestow ''survival advantages'' for an individual, or increase the the ability of the individual that has them to successfully reproduce offspring that can grow up and also reproduce, will tend to ''multiply'' over generations. | ||
Given enough time, this passive process can result in [[adaptation]]s and [[speciation]] (see [[evolution]]). Less drastically, natural selection accounts for the differing strains and breeds of plants and animals of the same species that are found in varying habitats and geographic regions. | Given enough time, this passive process can result in [[adaptation]]s and [[speciation]] (see [[evolution]]). Less drastically, natural selection accounts for the differing strains and breeds of plants and animals of the same species that are found in varying habitats and geographic regions. | ||
Line 15: | Line 15: | ||
== | ==General principles== | ||
Natural selection acts on the [[phenotype]]. The phenotype is the overall result of an individual's genetic make-up ([[genotype]]), the [[ecosystem|environment]], and the [[Epistasis|interactions between genes]] and between [[Gene-environment interaction|genes and the environment]]. Often, natural selection acts on specific traits of an individual, and the terms [[Genotype-phenotype distinction|phenotype and genotype]] are sometimes used narrowly to indicate these specific traits. | Natural selection acts on the [[phenotype]]. The phenotype is the overall result of an individual's genetic make-up ([[genotype]]), the [[ecosystem|environment]], and the [[Epistasis|interactions between genes]] and between [[Gene-environment interaction|genes and the environment]]. Often, natural selection acts on specific traits of an individual, and the terms [[Genotype-phenotype distinction|phenotype and genotype]] are sometimes used narrowly to indicate these specific traits. | ||
Some traits are determined by | Some traits are determined by a [[Mendelian inheritance|single gene]], but most are affected by many different genes. Variation in most of these genes has only a small effect on the phenotypic value of a trait, and the study of the genetics of these quantitative traits is called [[quantitative genetics]].<ref>Falconer DS & Mackay TFC (1996) ''Introduction to Quantitative Genetics'' Addison Wesley Longman, Harlow, Essex, UK ISBN 0-582-24302-5</ref> | ||
The key element in understanding natural selection is the concept of '''[[Fitness (biology)|fitness]]'''. Natural selection acts on individuals, but its ''average'' effect on all individuals with a particular genotype is the fitness of that genotype. Fitness is measured as the proportion of progeny that survives, multiplied by the average [[fecundity]], and it is equivalent to the ''[[reproductive success]]'' of a genotype. A fitness value of greater than one indicates that the frequency of that genotype in the population increases, while a value of less than one indicates that it decreases. The relative fitness of a genotype is estimated as the proportion of the fitness of a reference genotype. Related to relative fitness is the [[selection coefficient]], which is the difference between the relative fitness of two genotypes. The larger the selection coefficient, the stronger natural selection will act against the genotype with the lowest fitness. | The key element in understanding natural selection is the concept of '''[[Fitness (biology)|fitness]]'''. Natural selection acts on individuals, but its ''average'' effect on all individuals with a particular genotype is the fitness of that genotype. Fitness is measured as the proportion of progeny that survives, multiplied by the average [[fecundity]], and it is equivalent to the ''[[reproductive success]]'' of a genotype. A fitness value of greater than one indicates that the frequency of that genotype in the population increases, while a value of less than one indicates that it decreases. The relative fitness of a genotype is estimated as the proportion of the fitness of a reference genotype. Related to relative fitness is the [[selection coefficient]], which is the difference between the relative fitness of two genotypes. The larger the selection coefficient, the stronger natural selection will act against the genotype with the lowest fitness. | ||
Natural selection occurs at every life stage of an individual (see Figure 2), and selection at any of these stages can affect the likelihood that an individual will survive and reproduce. After an individual is born, it has to survive until adulthood before it can reproduce, and selection of those that reach this stage is called ''viability selection''. In many species, adults must compete with each other for mates (''[[sexual selection]]''), and success in this competition determines who will parent the next generation. When species reproduce more than once, a longer survival in the reproductive phase increases the number of offspring (''[[survival]] selection''). The fecundity of both females (e.g. how many eggs a female bird produces) and males (e.g. giant [[sperm]] in certain species of ''[[Drosophila]]''<ref>Pitnick S & Markow TA (1994) Large-male advantage associated with the costs of sperm production in ''Drosophila hydei'', a species with giant sperm. [[PNAS|''Proc Natl Acad Sci USA'']] 91:9277-81; Pitnick S (1996) Investment in testes and the cost of making long sperm in ''Drosophila''. [[American Naturalist|''Am Nat'']] 148:57-80</ref>) can be limited (''[[fecundity]] selection''). The viability of produced [[gamete]]s can differ, while [[intragenomic conflict]] (meiotic drive) between the [[haploid]] gametes can result in ''gametic'' or ''genic selection''. Finally, the union of some combinations of eggs and sperm might be more compatible that others (''compatibility selection''). | Natural selection occurs at every life stage of an individual (see Figure 2), and selection at any of these stages can affect the likelihood that an individual will survive and reproduce. After an individual is born, it has to survive until adulthood before it can reproduce, and selection of those that reach this stage is called ''viability selection''. In many species, adults must compete with each other for mates (''[[sexual selection]]''), and success in this competition determines who will parent the next generation. When species reproduce more than once, a longer survival in the reproductive phase increases the number of offspring (''[[survival]] selection''). The fecundity of both females (e.g. how many eggs a female bird produces) and males (e.g. giant [[sperm]] in certain species of ''[[Drosophila]]''<ref>Pitnick S & Markow TA (1994) Large-male advantage associated with the costs of sperm production in ''Drosophila hydei'', a species with giant sperm. [[PNAS|''Proc Natl Acad Sci USA'']] 91:9277-81; Pitnick S (1996) Investment in testes and the cost of making long sperm in ''Drosophila''. [[American Naturalist|''Am Nat'']] 148:57-80</ref>) can be limited (''[[fecundity]] selection''). | ||
The viability of produced [[gamete]]s can differ, while [[intragenomic conflict]] (meiotic drive) between the [[haploid]] gametes can result in ''gametic'' or ''genic selection''. Finally, the union of some combinations of eggs and sperm might be more compatible that others (''compatibility selection''). | |||
==="Ecological selection" and "sexual selection"=== | ==="Ecological selection" and "sexual selection"=== | ||
It is also useful to make a mechanistic distinction between [[ecological selection]] and [[sexual selection]]. ''Ecological selection'' covers any mechanism of selection as a result of the environment (including relatives | It is also useful to make a mechanistic distinction between [[ecological selection]] and the narrower term, [[sexual selection]]. ''Ecological selection'' covers any mechanism of selection as a result of the environment (including relatives, e.g. [[kin selection]], and conspecifics, e.g. [[Competition#Competition in biology and ecology|competition]] or [[infanticide]]). ''Sexual selection'' refers specifically to competition between conspecifics for mates <ref>{{cite book| author=Andersson, M| year=1995| title=Sexual Selection| publisher=Princeton University Press| location=Princeton, New Jersey| id=ISBN 0-691-00057-3}}</ref>. | ||
Sexual selection includes mechanisms such as ''mate choice'' and ''male-male competition'' although the two forms can act in combination in some species, when females choose the winners of the male-male competition. Mate choice, or ''intersexual selection'', typically involves ''female choice'', as it is usually the females who are most choosy, but in some sex-role reversed species it is the males that choose. Some features that are confined to one sex only of a particular species can be explained by selection exercised by the other sex in the choice of a mate, e.g. the extravagant plumage of some male birds. Aggression between members of the same sex (intrasexual selection) is typically referred to as ''male-male competition'', and is sometimes associated with very distinctive features, such as the antlers of stags, which are used in combat with other stags. More generally, intrasexual selection is often associated with [[sexual dimorphism]], including differences in body size between males and females of a species. | |||
Line 33: | Line 37: | ||
===Directionality of selection=== | ===Directionality of selection=== | ||
When | When some component of a variable trait is heritable, selection may alter the frequencies of the different [[allele]]s (variants of a gene) that are responsible for that variability. Selection can be divided into three classes: | ||
[[directional selection|Positive or directional selection]] | [[directional selection|Positive or directional selection]] occurs when a certain allele is associated with a greater fitness than others, resulting in an increase in frequency of that allele until it is fixed and the entire population expresses the fitter phenotype. | ||
Far more common is [[stabilizing selection|purifying or stabilizing selection]], which lowers the frequency of alleles which have a deleterious effect on the phenotype until they are eliminated from the population. Purifying selection results in functional genetic features (e.g. [[Protein biosynthesis|protein-coding sequences]] or [[regulatory sequence]]s) being [[conservation (genetics)|conserved]] over time. | Far more common is [[stabilizing selection|purifying or stabilizing selection]], which lowers the frequency of alleles which have a deleterious effect on the phenotype until they are eliminated from the population. Purifying selection results in functional genetic features (e.g. [[Protein biosynthesis|protein-coding sequences]] or [[regulatory sequence]]s) being [[conservation (genetics)|conserved]] over time because of selective pressure against deleterious variants. | ||
Finally, many forms of [[balancing selection]] do not result in fixation, but maintain an allele at intermediate frequencies in a population. This can happen in [[diploid]] species (with two pair of [[chromosome]]s) when individuals with a combination of two different alleles at a single [[Locus (genetics)|position at the chomosome]] ([[heterozygote]]) have a higher fitness than individuals that have two copies of the same allele ([[homozygote]]). This is called [[heterozygote advantage]] or overdominance. Allelic variation can also be maintained through [[disruptive selection|disruptive or diversifying selection]], which favors genotypes that depart from the average in either direction (that is, the opposite of overdominance), and can result in a [[bimodal distribution]] of trait values. Finally, it can occur by [[frequency-dependent selection]], where the fitness of one particular phenotype depends on the prevalence of other phenotypes in the population (see also [[Game theory]]). | Finally, many forms of [[balancing selection]] do not result in fixation, but maintain an allele at intermediate frequencies in a population. This can happen in [[diploid]] species (with two pair of [[chromosome]]s) when individuals with a combination of two different alleles at a single [[Locus (genetics)|position at the chomosome]] ([[heterozygote]]) have a higher fitness than individuals that have two copies of the same allele ([[homozygote]]). This is called [[heterozygote advantage]] or overdominance. Allelic variation can also be maintained through [[disruptive selection|disruptive or diversifying selection]], which favors genotypes that depart from the average in either direction (that is, the opposite of overdominance), and can result in a [[bimodal distribution]] of trait values. Finally, it can occur by [[frequency-dependent selection]], where the fitness of one particular phenotype depends on the prevalence of other phenotypes in the population (see also [[Game theory]]). |
Revision as of 18:54, 5 January 2007
Natural selection is the biological theory that explains why living creatures seem to match their environmental niches so well. Natural selection is a long term process underlies the "fit" between living creatures and their habitat, and accounts for the presence of drought tolerant plants in the desert and moisture-loving plants in the rain forest, heavily furred mammals are in the colder climates and lightly furred mammals in the warmer climes, XXXX and XXX. . The result of natural selection is change in the characteristics of species of plants, animals, and other organisms through the generations, to the creation of new species, and their further evolution.
The theory of natural selection, like all theories, makes certain assumptions. First, there is the premise that there is some variety between the individual examples of any particular kind of living thing. Second, there is the premise that at least some of those variations are features that can be inherited by the offspring of the individuals that possess them. Thirdly, there is the assumption that in any given situation, some characteristics make survival of that individual more likely, whereas other characteristics make that survival less likely. Finally, natural selection depends on the premise that there are variable characteristics that also serve to make reproduction of an individual more or less likely. Given all these assumptions, the theory of natural selection predicts that living things with heritable features that bestow survival advantages for an individual, or increase the the ability of the individual that has them to successfully reproduce offspring that can grow up and also reproduce, will tend to multiply over generations.
Given enough time, this passive process can result in adaptations and speciation (see evolution). Less drastically, natural selection accounts for the differing strains and breeds of plants and animals of the same species that are found in varying habitats and geographic regions.
The theory of natural selection is one of the cornerstones of modern biology. The term was introduced by Charles Darwin in his 1859 book The Origin of Species [1], by analogy with artificial selection, by which a farmer selects his breeding stock.
An example:
Background and context
General principles
Natural selection acts on the phenotype. The phenotype is the overall result of an individual's genetic make-up (genotype), the environment, and the interactions between genes and between genes and the environment. Often, natural selection acts on specific traits of an individual, and the terms phenotype and genotype are sometimes used narrowly to indicate these specific traits.
Some traits are determined by a single gene, but most are affected by many different genes. Variation in most of these genes has only a small effect on the phenotypic value of a trait, and the study of the genetics of these quantitative traits is called quantitative genetics.[2]
The key element in understanding natural selection is the concept of fitness. Natural selection acts on individuals, but its average effect on all individuals with a particular genotype is the fitness of that genotype. Fitness is measured as the proportion of progeny that survives, multiplied by the average fecundity, and it is equivalent to the reproductive success of a genotype. A fitness value of greater than one indicates that the frequency of that genotype in the population increases, while a value of less than one indicates that it decreases. The relative fitness of a genotype is estimated as the proportion of the fitness of a reference genotype. Related to relative fitness is the selection coefficient, which is the difference between the relative fitness of two genotypes. The larger the selection coefficient, the stronger natural selection will act against the genotype with the lowest fitness.
Natural selection occurs at every life stage of an individual (see Figure 2), and selection at any of these stages can affect the likelihood that an individual will survive and reproduce. After an individual is born, it has to survive until adulthood before it can reproduce, and selection of those that reach this stage is called viability selection. In many species, adults must compete with each other for mates (sexual selection), and success in this competition determines who will parent the next generation. When species reproduce more than once, a longer survival in the reproductive phase increases the number of offspring (survival selection). The fecundity of both females (e.g. how many eggs a female bird produces) and males (e.g. giant sperm in certain species of Drosophila[3]) can be limited (fecundity selection).
The viability of produced gametes can differ, while intragenomic conflict (meiotic drive) between the haploid gametes can result in gametic or genic selection. Finally, the union of some combinations of eggs and sperm might be more compatible that others (compatibility selection).
"Ecological selection" and "sexual selection"
It is also useful to make a mechanistic distinction between ecological selection and the narrower term, sexual selection. Ecological selection covers any mechanism of selection as a result of the environment (including relatives, e.g. kin selection, and conspecifics, e.g. competition or infanticide). Sexual selection refers specifically to competition between conspecifics for mates [4].
Sexual selection includes mechanisms such as mate choice and male-male competition although the two forms can act in combination in some species, when females choose the winners of the male-male competition. Mate choice, or intersexual selection, typically involves female choice, as it is usually the females who are most choosy, but in some sex-role reversed species it is the males that choose. Some features that are confined to one sex only of a particular species can be explained by selection exercised by the other sex in the choice of a mate, e.g. the extravagant plumage of some male birds. Aggression between members of the same sex (intrasexual selection) is typically referred to as male-male competition, and is sometimes associated with very distinctive features, such as the antlers of stags, which are used in combat with other stags. More generally, intrasexual selection is often associated with sexual dimorphism, including differences in body size between males and females of a species.
Genetical theory of natural selection
Natural selection by itself is a simple concept, in which fitness differences between phenotypes are crucial. However, its explanatory power comes from understanding the interplay of the selection mechanism with the underlying genetics.
Directionality of selection
When some component of a variable trait is heritable, selection may alter the frequencies of the different alleles (variants of a gene) that are responsible for that variability. Selection can be divided into three classes:
Positive or directional selection occurs when a certain allele is associated with a greater fitness than others, resulting in an increase in frequency of that allele until it is fixed and the entire population expresses the fitter phenotype.
Far more common is purifying or stabilizing selection, which lowers the frequency of alleles which have a deleterious effect on the phenotype until they are eliminated from the population. Purifying selection results in functional genetic features (e.g. protein-coding sequences or regulatory sequences) being conserved over time because of selective pressure against deleterious variants.
Finally, many forms of balancing selection do not result in fixation, but maintain an allele at intermediate frequencies in a population. This can happen in diploid species (with two pair of chromosomes) when individuals with a combination of two different alleles at a single position at the chomosome (heterozygote) have a higher fitness than individuals that have two copies of the same allele (homozygote). This is called heterozygote advantage or overdominance. Allelic variation can also be maintained through disruptive or diversifying selection, which favors genotypes that depart from the average in either direction (that is, the opposite of overdominance), and can result in a bimodal distribution of trait values. Finally, it can occur by frequency-dependent selection, where the fitness of one particular phenotype depends on the prevalence of other phenotypes in the population (see also Game theory).
Selection and genetic variation
Some genetic variation is functionally neutral; i.e., it produces no phenotypic effect or significant differences in fitness. Previously, this was thought to encompass most of the genetic variation in non-coding DNA, but parts of those sequences are highly conserved, indicating that they are under strong purifying selection, and suggesting that mutations in these regions have deleterious consequences[5]. When genetic variation does not result in differences in fitness, selection cannot directly affect the frequency of such variation. As a result, the genetic variation at those sites will be higher than at sites where selection does have a result.
Genetic linkage
Genetic linkage occurs when two alleles are close to each other. During the formation of the gametes, recombination of the genetic material results in a reshuffling of the alleles. However, the chance that such a reshuffle occurs between two alleles depends on the distance between those alleles; the closer the alleles are to each other, the less likely it is that such a reshuffle will occur. Consequently, when selection targets one allele, this automatically results in selection of the other allele as well; through this mechanism, selection can have a strong influence on patterns of variation in the genome.
Mutation-selection balance
Natural selection results in less genetic variation by eliminating maladapted individuals and, through that, the mutations that causes the maladaptation. At the same time, new mutations arise spontaneously, resulting in a mutation-selection balance. The exact outcome depends both on the rate at which new mutations occur and on the strength of the natural selection.
Selective sweep
Selective sweeps occur when an allele becomes more common in a population as a result of positive selection. As the prevalence of one allele increases, linked alleles (those nearby on the chromosome) can also become more common, whether they are neutral or even slightly deleterious. This is called genetic hitchhiking. A strong selective sweep results in a region of the genome where the positively selected haplotype (the allele and its neighbours) are essentially the only ones that exist in the population.
Whether a selective sweep has occurred or not can be investigated by measuring linkage disequilibrium, i.e., whether a given haplotype is overrepresented in the population. Normally, genetic recombination results in a 'reshuffle' of the alleles within a haplotype, and none of the haplotypes will dominate the population. However, during a selective sweep, selection for a specific allele will also result in selection of neighbouring alleles. Therefore, the presence of strong linkage disequilibrium might indicate that there has been a 'recent' selective sweep, and this can be used to identify sites recently under selection.
Background selection
Background selection is the opposite of a selective sweep. If a specific site experiences strong and persistent purifying selection (perhaps as a result of mutation-selection balance), linked variation will tend to be weeded out along with it. However, background selection acts as a result of new mutations, which can occur randomly in any haplotype. It therefore produces no linkage disequilibrium, although it reduces the amount of variation in the region.
Evolution by means of natural selection
A prerequisite for natural selection to result in adaptive evolution, novel traits and speciation, is the presence of heritable genetic variation that results in fitness differences. Genetic variation is the result of mutations, recombinations and alterations in the karyotype (the number, shape, size and internal arrangement of the chromosomes). Any of these changes might have an effect that is highly advantageous or highly disadvantageous, but large effects are very rare. In the past, most changes in the genetic material were considered neutral or close to neutral because they occurred in noncoding DNA or resulted in a synonymous substitution. However, recent research suggests that many mutations in non-coding DNA do have slight deleterious effects[5][6]. Overall, of those mutations that do affect the fitness of the individual, most are slightly deleterious, some reduce the fitness dramatically and some increase the fitness.
By the definition of fitness, individuals with greater fitness are more likely to contribute offspring to the next generation, while individuals with lesser fitness are more likely to die early or they fail to reproduce. As a result, alleles which on average result in greater fitness become more abundant in the next generation, while alleles which generally reduce fitness become rarer. If the selection forces remain the same for many generations, beneficial alleles become more and more abundant, until they dominate the population, while alleles with a lesser fitness disappear. In every generation, new mutations and recombinations arise spontaneously, producing a new spectrum of phenotypes. Therefore, each new generation will be enriched by the increasing abundance of alleles that contribute to those traits that were favored by selection, enhancing these traits over successive generations.
Some mutations occur in so-called regulatory genes. Changes in these can have large effects on the phenotype of the individual because they regulate the function of many other genes. Most, but not all, mutations in regulatory genes result in non-viable zygotes. For example, mutations in some HOX genes in humans result in an increase in the number of fingers or toes[7] or a cervical rib[8]. When such mutations result in a higher fitness, natural selection will favor these phenotypes and the novel trait will spread in the population.
Established traits are not immutable: an established trait may lose its fitness if environmental conditions change. In these circumstances, in the absence of natural selection to preserve the trait, the trait will become more variable and will deteriorate over time. The power of natural selection will also inevitably depend upon prevailing environmental factors; in general, the number of offspring is (far) greater than the number of individuals that can survive to the next generation, and there will be intense selection of the best adapted individuals for the next generation.
Speciation
Speciation requires selective mating, which result in a reduced gene flow. Selective mating can be the result of, for example, a change in the physical environment (physical isolation by an extrinsic barrier), or by sexual selection resulting in assortative mating. Over time, these subgroups might diverge radically to become different species, either because of differences in selection pressures on the different subgroups, or because different mutations arise spontaneously in the different populations, or because of founder effects - some potentially beneficial alleles may, by chance, be present in only one or other of two subgroups when they first become separated. When the genetic changes result in increasing incompatibility between the genotypes of the two subgroups, gene flow between the groups will be reduced even more, and will stop altogether as soon as the mutations become fixed in the respective subgroups. As few as two mutations can result in speciation: if each mutation has a neutral or positive effect on fitness when they occur separately, but a negative effect when they occur together, then fixation of these genes in the respective subgroups will lead to two reproductively isolated populations. According to the biological species concept, these will be two different species.
Until the early 19th century, the established view in Western societies was that differences between individuals of a species were uninteresting departures from their Platonic ideal (or typus) of created kinds. However, growing awareness of the fossil record led to the recognition that species that lived in the distant past were often very different from those that exist today. In the early years of the 19th century, radical evolutionists such as Jean Baptiste Lamarck had proposed that characteristics (adaptations) acquired by individuals might be inherited by their progeny, causing, in enough time, transmutation of species (see Lamarckism).[9]
Between 1842 and 1844, Charles Darwin outlined his theory of evolution by natural selection as an explanation for adaptation and speciation. He defined natural selection as the "principle by which each slight variation [of a trait], if useful, is preserved". The concept was simple but powerful: individuals best adapted to their environments are more likely to survive and reproduce. As long as there is some variation between them, there will be an inevitable selection of individuals with the most advantageous variations. If the variations are inherited, then differential reproductive success will lead to a progressive evolution of particular populations of a species, and populations that evolve to be sufficiently different might eventually become different species.
Darwin thought of natural selection by analogy to how farmers select crops or livestock for breeding (artificial selection); in his early manuscripts he referred to a 'Nature' which would do the selection. In the next twenty years, he shared these theories with just a few friends, while gathering evidence and trying to address all possible objections. In 1858, Alfred Russel Wallace[10], a young naturalist, independently conceived the principle and described it in a letter to Darwin. Not wanting to be scooped, Darwin contacted scientific friends to find an honorable way to handle this potentially embarrassing situation, and two short papers by the two were read at the Linnean Society announcing co-discovery of the principle. The following year, Darwin published The Origin of Species, along with his evidence and detailed discussion. This became a topic of great dispute; evolutionary theories became the primary way of talking about speciation, but natural selection did not predominate as the mechanism by which it happened. What made natural selection controversial was doubt about whether it was powerful enough to result in speciation, and that it was 'unguided' rather than 'progressive', something that even Darwin's supporters balked at.
Darwin's ideas were inspired by the observations that he had made on the Voyage of the Beagle, and by the economic theories of Thomas Malthus, who noted that population (if unchecked) increases exponentially whereas the food supply grows only arithmetically; thus limitations of resources would inevitably lead to a "struggle for existence", in which only the fittest would survive. Similar ideas go back to ancient times; the Ionian physician Empedocles said that many races "must have been unable to beget and continue their kind. For in the case of every species that exists, either craft or courage or speed has from the beginning of its existence protected and preserved it". Several eighteenth-century thinkers wrote about similar theories, including Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis in 1745, Lord Monboddo in his theories of species alteration, and Darwin's grandfather Erasmus Darwin in 1794–1796. In the 6th edition of The Origin of Species Darwin acknowledged that others — notably William Charles Wells in 1813, and Patrick Matthew in 1831 — had proposed similar theories, but had not presented them fully or in notable scientific publications. Wells presented his hypothesis to explain the origin of human races in person at the Royal Society, and Matthew published his as an appendix to his book on arboriculture[11]. Edward Blyth had also proposed a method of natural selection as a mechanism of keeping species constant. However, these 'precursors' had little influence on evolutionary thought.
Within a decade of The Origin of Species, most educated people had begun to accept that evolution had occurred in some form or another. However, of the many ideas of evolution that emerged, only August Weismann's saw natural selection as the main evolutionary force. Even T.H. Huxley believed that there was more "purpose" in evolution than natural selection afforded, and neo-Lamarckism was also popular. After reading Darwin, Herbert Spencer introduced the term survival of the fittest; this became popular, and Wallace marked up an entire edition of The Origin of Species, replacing every instance of natural selection with Spencer's phrase. Although the phrase is still often used by non-biologists, modern biologists avoid it because it is tautological if fittest is read to mean functionally superior.
Modern evolutionary synthesis
Only after the integration of a theory of evolution with a complex statistical appreciation of Mendel's 're-discovered' laws of inheritance did natural selection become generally accepted by scientists. The work of Ronald Fisher, who first tried to explain natural selection by the underlying genetic processes[12]); J.B.S. Haldane, who introduced the concept of the 'cost' of natural selection [13]; Sewall Wright, one of the founders of population genetics [14]; Theodosius Dobzhansky, who established the idea that mutation, by creating genetic diversity, supplied the raw material for natural selection[15]), William Hamilton, who conceived of kin selection; Ernst Mayr, who recognised the importance of reproductive isolation for speciation[16] and many others formed the modern evolutionary synthesis. This propelled natural selection to the forefront of evolutionary theories, where it remains today.
Impact of the idea
Darwin's ideas, along with those of Adam Smith and Karl Marx, had a profound influence on 19th-century thought. Perhaps the most radical claim of the theory of evolution through natural selection is that "elaborately constructed forms, so different from each other, and dependent on each other in so complex a manner" evolved from the simplest forms of life by a few simple principles. This claim inspired some of Darwin's most ardent supporters—and provoked the most profound opposition. The radicalism of natural selection, according to Stephen Jay Gould [17], lay in its power to "dethrone some of the deepest and most traditional comforts of Western thought". In particular, it challenged beliefs in nature's benevolence, order, and good design, the belief that humans occupy a summit of power and excellence, belief in an omnipotent, benevolent creator, and belief that nature has any meaningful direction, or that humans fit into any sensible pattern.
Energetic theory
In 1922, Alfred Lotka proposed that natural selection might be understood as a physical principle which can be energetically quantified.[18][19] Through the work of Howard T. Odum this became known as the maximum power principle whereby evolutionary systems with selective advantage maximise the rate of useful energy transformation.
References
- ↑ Darwin C (1859) On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life John Murray, London; modern reprint Charles Darwin, Julian Huxley (2003). The Origin of Species. Signet Classics. ISBN 0-451-52906-5.
- ↑ Falconer DS & Mackay TFC (1996) Introduction to Quantitative Genetics Addison Wesley Longman, Harlow, Essex, UK ISBN 0-582-24302-5
- ↑ Pitnick S & Markow TA (1994) Large-male advantage associated with the costs of sperm production in Drosophila hydei, a species with giant sperm. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 91:9277-81; Pitnick S (1996) Investment in testes and the cost of making long sperm in Drosophila. Am Nat 148:57-80
- ↑ Andersson, M (1995). Sexual Selection. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-00057-3.
- ↑ 5.0 5.1 Kryukov GV et al (2005) Small fitness effect of mutations in highly conserved non-coding regions. Human Molecular Genetics 14:2221-9; Bejerano G et al (2004) Ultraconserved elements in the human genome. Science 304:1321-5
- ↑ Cite error: Invalid
<ref>
tag; no text was provided for refs namedNCFitnessEffects2
- ↑ Zakany J, FromentalRamain C, Warot X & Duboule D (1997) Regulation of number and size of digits by posterior Hox genes: a dose-dependent mechanism with potential evolutionary implications. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 94:13695-700
- ↑ Galis F (1999) Why do almost all mammals have seven cervical vertebrae? developmental constraints, Hox genes, and cancer. J Exp Zool 285:19-26
- ↑ Chevalier de Lamarck J-B, de Monet PA (1809) Philosophie Zoologique
- ↑ Wallace, Alfred Russel (1870) Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection New York: Macmillan & Co. [1]
- ↑ Dempster WJ (1996) Evolutionary concepts in the nineteeth century, natural selection and Patrick Matthew. Durham: The Pentland Press. ISBN 185213568 Template:Please check ISBN
- ↑ Cite error: Invalid
<ref>
tag; no text was provided for refs namedfisher
- ↑ Haldane JBS (1932) The Causes of Evolution; Haldane JBS (1957) The cost of natural selection. J Genet 55:511-24([2]
- ↑ Wright S (1932) The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding and selection in evolution] Proc 6th Int Cong Genet 1:356–66
- ↑ Dobzhansky Th (1937) Genetics and the Origin of Species Columbia University Press, New York. (2nd ed. 1941; 3rd edn. 1951)
- ↑ Mayr E (1942) Systematics and the Origin of Species Columbia University Press, New York. ISBN 0-674-86250-3
- ↑ The New York Review of Books: Darwinian Fundamentalism (accessed May 6, 2006)
- ↑ Lotka AJ (1922a) Contribution to the energetics of evolution [PDF] Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 8:147–51
- ↑ Lotka AJ (1922b) Natural selection as a physical principle [PDF] Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 8:151–4
Further reading
- For general audiences
- Dawkins R, (1996) Climbing Mount Improbable Penguin Books, ISBN 0-670-85018-7
- Dennett D (1995) Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life Simon & Schuster ISBN 0-684-82471-X
- Gould SJ (1997) Ever Since Darwin: Reflections in Natural History Norton, ISBN 0-393-06425-5
- Jones S (2001) Darwin's Ghost: The Origin of Species Updated Ballantine Books ISBN 0-345-42277-5. Also published in Britain under the title Almost like a whale: the origin of species updated Doubleday. ISBN 1-86230-025-9
- Lewontin RC (1978) Adaptation. Scientific American 239:212-30
- Weiner, J. (1994) The Beak of the Finch: A Story of Evolution in Our Time, Vintage Books, ISBN 0-679-73337-X
- For more advanced audiences
- Gould SJ (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-00613-5.
- Maynard Smith J (1993) The Theory of Evolution Cambridge University Press
- Popper K (1978) Natural selection and the emergence of mind. Dialectica 32:339-55. See [3]
- Sargent TD, Millar CD, Lambert DM (1998) The "classical" explanation of industrial melanism: Assessing the evidence. Evolutionary Biology 30:299-322.
- Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought Oxford University Press.
- Williams GC (1992) Natural Selection: Domains, Levels and Challenges Oxford University Press.
- Historical
- Kohm M (2004) A Reason for Everything: Natural Selection and the English Imagination London: Faber and Faber. ISBN 0-571-22392-3. For review, see [4] van Wyhe J (2005) Human Nature Review 5:1-4
External links
- Evolution by Natural Selection - An introduction to the logic of the theory of natural selection
- Natural selection: how evolution works Interview with Douglas J. Futuyma
- The Origin of Species by Charles Darwin - Chapter 4,Natural Selection
- Natural Selection- Modeling for Understanding in Science Education, University of Wisconsin
- natural selection from University of Berkeley education website
See also
- Co-evolution
- Gene-centered view of evolution
- Genetic algorithm
- Negative selection
- Ring species
- Unit of selection