Schröder-Bernstein theorem/Citable Version: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>D. Matt Innis
 
imported>John Stephenson
 
(2 intermediate revisions by one other user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
#REDIRECT [[Schröder-Bernstein theorem/Draft]]
{{subpages}}  {{TOC|right}}
 
The '''Schröder-Bernstein theorem''' (sometimes '''Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem''') is a fundamental theorem of [[set theory]].
Essentially, it states that if two sets are such that each one has at least as many elements as the other
then the two sets have equally many elements.
Though this assertion may seem obvious it needs a proof, and it is crucial for the definition of [[cardinality]] to make sense.
 
'''Remark:'''
In analogy to this theorem the term [[Schröder-Bernstein property]] is used
in other contexts to describe similar properties.
 
== The Schröder-Bernstein theorem ==
 
'''Theorem.'''
If for two sets ''A'' and ''B'' there are
an injective function from ''A'' into ''B'' and an injective function from ''B'' into ''A''
then there is a bijective function from ''A'' onto ''B''.
 
In terms of [[cardinal number]]s this is equivalent to:
 
'''Corollary.'''
If |''A''| ≤ |''B''| and |''B''| ≤ |''A''| then |''A''| = |''B''|.
 
Here |''A''| and |''B''| denote the cardinal numbers corresponding to the sets ''A'' and ''B''.
<br>
The corollary shows that &le; is a partial [[order relation|order]] for cardinal numbers.
(The order is indeed a linear order, but this aspect is not touched by the theorem
since the existence of injective functions between the two sets is assumed in its statement.)
 
'''Remark.'''
It is of theoretical interest that the proof of the theorem does not depend on the [[Axiom of Choice]].
 
== History ==
 
As it is often the case in mathematics, the name of this theorem does not truly reflect its history.
The traditional name "Schröder-Bernstein" is based on two proofs published independently in 1898.
Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1895,
while Schröder's name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed
while the name of the mathematician who first proved it is not connected with the theorem.
 
{{Image|Cantor1895.MA46.484-BC.jpg|right|600px|Georg Cantor (1895) states the theorem (B.)}}
 
In reality, the history was more complicated:
* '''1887''' [[Richard Dedekind]] proves the theorem but does not publish it.
* '''1895''' [[Georg Cantor]] states the theorem in his first paper on set theory and transfinite numbers (as an easy consequence of the linear order of cardinal numbers which he was going to prove later).
* '''1896''' [[Ernst Schröder]] announces a proof (as a corollary of a more general statement).
* '''1897''' [[Felix Bernstein]], a young student in Cantor's Seminar, presents his proof.
* '''1897''' After a visit by Bernstein, Dedekind independently proves it a second time.
* '''1898''' Bernstein's proof is published by [[Émile Borel]] in his book on functions. (Communicated by Cantor at the 1897 congress in Zürich.)
 
Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous memoir ''Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?''
and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor's paper:
:<math>
        A \subset B \subset C \quad\textrm{and}\quad |A|=|C| \qquad\Rightarrow\qquad |A|=|B|=|C|
</math>
Cantor observed this property as early as 1882/83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers
and therefore (implicitly) relying on the Axiom of Choice.
 
== Proof ==
 
The bijective function between the two sets can be explicitly constructed from the two injective functions given.
Therefore the Axiom of Choice is not needed in the proof.
(There are many versions of the proof.)
 
=== Outline ===
 
We denote by ''f'' the injective function from ''A'' to ''B'', and by ''g'' the injective function from ''B'' to ''A''.
 
The proof is based on a simple observation:
<br>
If ''A'' is the disjoint union of two sets, ''A''<sub>1</sub> and ''A''<sub>2</sub>, and ''B'' the disjoint union of two sets, ''B''<sub>1</sub> and ''B''<sub>2</sub>,
such that ''B''<sub>1</sub> is the image of ''A''<sub>1</sub> under ''f'' and ''A''<sub>2</sub> is the image of ''B''<sub>2</sub> under ''g''
then a bijection from ''A'' onto ''B'' is obtained by taking ''f'' on ''A''<sub>1</sub> and ''g''<sup>&minus;1</sup> on ''A''<sub>2</sub>.
 
Such a dissection is characterized by the property that the following process,
if performed on ''A''<sub>1</sub>, gives ''A''<sub>1</sub> as a result. (Thus ''A''<sub>1</sub> is a ''fixed point''.)
: Take a subset of ''A'', find its image under ''f'' in ''B'', take the complement, find its image under ''g'' in ''A'', and, finally, take the complement.
This defines a mapping of subsets of ''A'' to subsets of ''A'' that is increasing, and such a mapping always has a fixed point.
 
=== Proof ===
 
By assumption, there are injective functions
: <math> f : A \to B \quad\text{and}\quad g : B \to A </math>
They induce two (injective) image mappings between the power sets
: <math> f_\ast : \mathcal P(A) \to \mathcal P(B) \quad\text{and}\quad
        g_\ast : \mathcal P(B) \to \mathcal P(A) </math>
The mapping
: <math>
  \sigma (S) := A \setminus g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (S) ) \quad ( S \subset A )
  </math>
on the power set of ''A'' is monotone increasing
: <math>  S_1 \subset S \subset A
          \Rightarrow \sigma (S_1) \subset \sigma (S)
  </math>
and
: <math>  A_1 := \bigcap \{ \sigma(S) \mid \sigma(S) \subset S \subset A \}
  </math>
is a fixed point of &sigma;
: <math>  \sigma (A_1) = A_1  </math>
Thus the function ''h'' defined as
: <math>  h (a) := \begin{cases}      f(a)  &  a \in A_1              \\
                                g^{-1}(a)  &  a \in A \setminus A_1  \\ \end{cases}
  </math>
is a bijective function between ''A'' and ''B''.
 
=== Details ===
 
(1) Recalling the definition of the ''image'' of a set under a [[function (mathematics)|function]], the induced image mappings are
: <math> f_\ast (S) := \{ f(s) | s \in S \} \quad ( S \subset A )
        \quad\text{and}\quad
        g_\ast (T) := \{ g(t) | t \in T \} \quad ( T \subset B )
</math>
 
(2) &sigma; is a monotone increasing function on the power set of ''A'':
: <math>
  S_1 \subset S
  \Rightarrow f_\ast (S_1) \subset f_\ast (S)
  \Rightarrow B \setminus f_\ast (S_1) \supset B \setminus f_\ast (S)
</math>
:: <math>
  \Rightarrow g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (S_1) ) \supset g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (S) )
</math>
:: <math>
\Rightarrow
  \sigma (S_1) := A \setminus ( g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (S_1) ) )
  \subset  A \setminus ( g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (S) ) ) =: \sigma (S)
</math>
 
(3) Any monotone increasing function on a power set has a fixed point ''A''<sub>1</sub>:
: <math>  \sigma(A) \in \mathcal A := \{ \sigma(S) \mid \sigma(S) \subset S \subset A \}
          \Rightarrow \mathcal A \not= \emptyset
</math>
 
: <math>  (\forall \sigma(S) \in \mathcal A ) A_1 \subset \sigma(S) \subset S
          \Rightarrow  \sigma (A_1) \subset \sigma^2 (S) \subset \sigma(S) \in \mathcal A
</math>
:: <math>
          \Rightarrow  \sigma (A_1) \subset \bigcap \mathcal A = A_1
          \Rightarrow  \sigma(A_1) \in \mathcal A
          \Rightarrow  \sigma (A_1) \supset \bigcap \mathcal A = A_1
</math>
: <math>
          \Rightarrow  \sigma (A_1) = A_1
  </math>
 
(4) ''h'' is well-defined and injective because ''f'' and ''g'' are injective and ''g''<sup>&minus;1</sup> is defined on the complement of ''A''<sub>1</sub>:
: <math>
  A \setminus ( g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (A_1) ) ) = \sigma (A_1) = A_1 = A \setminus ( A \setminus A_1 )
</math>
:: <math> 
  \Rightarrow  g_\ast ( B \setminus f_\ast (A_1) ) =  A \setminus A_1
  </math>
: Moreover, this also shows that ''h'' is bijective because it follows that the image of A under ''h'' is
:: <math> 
    f_\ast (A_1) \cup g^{-1} ( A \setminus A_1 ) = f_\ast (A_1) \cup ( B \setminus f_\ast (A_1) ) = B
  </math>
 
: In other words, ''A''<sub>1</sub> induces a decomposition of ''A'' and ''B'' as described in the outline of the proof:
:: <math>
          A_1                    , \qquad
          A_2 := A \setminus A_1 , \qquad
          B_1 := f_\ast (A_1)    , \qquad
          B_2 := B \setminus B_1
  </math>
 
: that has the desired properties.

Latest revision as of 14:34, 23 September 2013

This article has a Citable Version.
Main Article
Discussion
Related Articles  [?]
Bibliography  [?]
External Links  [?]
Citable Version  [?]
 
This version approved either by the Approvals Committee, or an Editor from the listed workgroup. The Mathematics Workgroup is responsible for this citable version. While we have done conscientious work, we cannot guarantee that this version is wholly free of mistakes. See here (not History) for authorship.
Help improve this work further on the editable Main Article!

The Schröder-Bernstein theorem (sometimes Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem) is a fundamental theorem of set theory. Essentially, it states that if two sets are such that each one has at least as many elements as the other then the two sets have equally many elements. Though this assertion may seem obvious it needs a proof, and it is crucial for the definition of cardinality to make sense.

Remark: In analogy to this theorem the term Schröder-Bernstein property is used in other contexts to describe similar properties.

The Schröder-Bernstein theorem

Theorem. If for two sets A and B there are an injective function from A into B and an injective function from B into A then there is a bijective function from A onto B.

In terms of cardinal numbers this is equivalent to:

Corollary. If |A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |A| then |A| = |B|.

Here |A| and |B| denote the cardinal numbers corresponding to the sets A and B.
The corollary shows that ≤ is a partial order for cardinal numbers. (The order is indeed a linear order, but this aspect is not touched by the theorem since the existence of injective functions between the two sets is assumed in its statement.)

Remark. It is of theoretical interest that the proof of the theorem does not depend on the Axiom of Choice.

History

As it is often the case in mathematics, the name of this theorem does not truly reflect its history. The traditional name "Schröder-Bernstein" is based on two proofs published independently in 1898. Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1895, while Schröder's name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed while the name of the mathematician who first proved it is not connected with the theorem.

Georg Cantor (1895) states the theorem (B.)

In reality, the history was more complicated:

  • 1887 Richard Dedekind proves the theorem but does not publish it.
  • 1895 Georg Cantor states the theorem in his first paper on set theory and transfinite numbers (as an easy consequence of the linear order of cardinal numbers which he was going to prove later).
  • 1896 Ernst Schröder announces a proof (as a corollary of a more general statement).
  • 1897 Felix Bernstein, a young student in Cantor's Seminar, presents his proof.
  • 1897 After a visit by Bernstein, Dedekind independently proves it a second time.
  • 1898 Bernstein's proof is published by Émile Borel in his book on functions. (Communicated by Cantor at the 1897 congress in Zürich.)

Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous memoir Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor's paper:

Cantor observed this property as early as 1882/83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers and therefore (implicitly) relying on the Axiom of Choice.

Proof

The bijective function between the two sets can be explicitly constructed from the two injective functions given. Therefore the Axiom of Choice is not needed in the proof. (There are many versions of the proof.)

Outline

We denote by f the injective function from A to B, and by g the injective function from B to A.

The proof is based on a simple observation:
If A is the disjoint union of two sets, A1 and A2, and B the disjoint union of two sets, B1 and B2, such that B1 is the image of A1 under f and A2 is the image of B2 under g then a bijection from A onto B is obtained by taking f on A1 and g−1 on A2.

Such a dissection is characterized by the property that the following process, if performed on A1, gives A1 as a result. (Thus A1 is a fixed point.)

Take a subset of A, find its image under f in B, take the complement, find its image under g in A, and, finally, take the complement.

This defines a mapping of subsets of A to subsets of A that is increasing, and such a mapping always has a fixed point.

Proof

By assumption, there are injective functions

They induce two (injective) image mappings between the power sets

The mapping

on the power set of A is monotone increasing

and

is a fixed point of σ

Thus the function h defined as

is a bijective function between A and B.

Details

(1) Recalling the definition of the image of a set under a function, the induced image mappings are

(2) σ is a monotone increasing function on the power set of A:

(3) Any monotone increasing function on a power set has a fixed point A1:

(4) h is well-defined and injective because f and g are injective and g−1 is defined on the complement of A1:

Moreover, this also shows that h is bijective because it follows that the image of A under h is
In other words, A1 induces a decomposition of A and B as described in the outline of the proof:
that has the desired properties.