Ontological argument for the existence of God: Difference between revisions

From Citizendium
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Peter J. King
m (link)
imported>Peter J. King
Line 13: Line 13:
==Mediæval versions==
==Mediæval versions==
===Anselm of Canterbury===
===Anselm of Canterbury===
[[Anselm of Canterbury]] (1033–1109) introduced the ontological argument to the Christian world in Chapter 2 of his ''[[Proslogion]]''.  The concept with which he starts is that of a being than which no greater can be conceived.  He then refers to the "fool" who "hath said in his heart, there is no God" (''[[Psalms]]'' xiv 1), and argues that the fool at least understands the concept of a being than which no greater can be conceived.  Now he brings out the contradiction, for the fool must understand the being than which no greater can be conceived as existing only in his understanding — but then he could also conceive of that being as existing reality, and that would be a greater being than the one just in his understanding. How could there be a being greater than a being than which no greater can be conceived?  Therefore, a being than which no greater can be conceived must exist both in the understanding and in reality.
[[Anselm of Canterbury]] (1033–1109) introduced the ontological argument to the Christian world in Chapter II of his ''[[Proslogion]]''.  The concept with which he starts is that of a being than which no greater can be conceived.  He then refers to the "fool" who "hath said in his heart, there is no God" (''[[Psalms]]'' xiv 1), and argues that the fool at least understands the concept of a being than which no greater can be conceived.  Now he brings out the contradiction, for the fool must understand the being than which no greater can be conceived as existing only in his understanding — but then he could also conceive of that being as existing reality, and that would be a greater being than the one just in his understanding. How could there be a being greater than a being than which no greater can be conceived?  Therefore, a being than which no greater can be conceived must exist both in the understanding and in reality.
 
In Chapter III of ''Proslogion'', Aquinas goes on to argue that God – the being than which no greater can be conceived – [[Necessity (philosophy)|necessarily] exists (cannot be conceived not to exist), because a being that cannot be conceived not to exist is greater than one which can be conceived not to exist (a [[Contntingency (philosophy)|contingent]] being).  Thus, he says, God exists "more truly than all other beings, and hence in a less degree".


==Early-modern versions==
==Early-modern versions==

Revision as of 05:05, 16 March 2007

An ontological argument sets out to prove the existence of the God of the monotheistic religions from the nature of concepts alone. It is thus an a priori argument. The term "ontological argument" originates with Immanuel Kant (who rejected the argument form), though it can be traced, in various forms, back to the work of Aristotle.

The argument typically works via a reductio ad absurdum: it presents a certain concept (for example that of a maximally perfect being — a being that has every possible perfection), supposes that such a being does not exist, and then draws out a contradiction, thus proving that such a being exists. That being is then identified with God. In other words, the concept implies its own instantiation; if one grasps the concept of God, then one is committed to the existence of God. (A separate argument is needed to show that there can be only one instantiation of the concept — only one God.)

The best-known uses of the argument are to be found in the context of the Abrahamic religions, its earliest formulation being found in the Proslogion of the eleventh-century philosopher and theologian Anselm of Canterbury. It was rejected and argued against by the thirteenth-century philosopher and theologian Thomas Aquinas, and was for some time neglected, but the early modern period saw its revival. René Descartes presented what became probably the best-known form of the argument, but versions were devised by prominent philosophers such as Gottfried Leibniz and Baruch Spinoza. In the modern period, attempts have been made to devise up-dated versions of the argument, most notably by Norman Malcolm, Charles Hartshorne, and Alvin Plantinga.

Anselm's version was criticised by Aquinas and by Anselm's contemporary, Gaunilo. Descartes' version was criticised by many of his contemporaries, including Caterus and Pierre Gassendi, and later by such philosophers as as Kant, David Hume, and Gottlob Frege.

The differences between the different versions of the argument are generally a matter of the precise nature of the starting concept.

Aristotle

Mediæval versions

Anselm of Canterbury

Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109) introduced the ontological argument to the Christian world in Chapter II of his Proslogion. The concept with which he starts is that of a being than which no greater can be conceived. He then refers to the "fool" who "hath said in his heart, there is no God" (Psalms xiv 1), and argues that the fool at least understands the concept of a being than which no greater can be conceived. Now he brings out the contradiction, for the fool must understand the being than which no greater can be conceived as existing only in his understanding — but then he could also conceive of that being as existing reality, and that would be a greater being than the one just in his understanding. How could there be a being greater than a being than which no greater can be conceived? Therefore, a being than which no greater can be conceived must exist both in the understanding and in reality.

In Chapter III of Proslogion, Aquinas goes on to argue that God – the being than which no greater can be conceived – [[Necessity (philosophy)|necessarily] exists (cannot be conceived not to exist), because a being that cannot be conceived not to exist is greater than one which can be conceived not to exist (a contingent being). Thus, he says, God exists "more truly than all other beings, and hence in a less degree".

Early-modern versions

René Descartes

Baruch Spinoza

Gottfried Leibniz

Modern versions

Norman Malcolm

Charles Hartshorne

Alvin Plantinga

Notes


Bibliography

  • Anselm of Canterbury (translated by Jonathan Barnes) Anselm's Proslogium or Discourse on the Existence of God. David Banach's Web site.
  • Charles Hartshorne The Logic of Perfection. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court, 1962.
  • Norman Malcolm "Anselm's Ontological Arguments". Philosophical Review 69:1 (1960), pp 41–62. Reprinted in his Knowledge and Certainty: Essays and Lectures by Norman Malcolm. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1975. ISBN 0801491541 (also in Plantinga [1965]).
  • Alvin Plantinga The Ontological Argument from St Anselm to Contemporary Philosophers. Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1965.
  • Alvin Plantinga God, Freedom, and Evil. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans, 1977.

External links